U.S. flag

An official website of the United States government

The .gov means it’s official. Federal government websites often end in .gov or .mil. Before sharing sensitive information, make sure you’re on a federal government site.

The site is secure. The https:// ensures that you are connecting to the official website and that any information you provide is encrypted and transmitted securely.

  • Publications
  • Account settings

Preview improvements coming to the PMC website in October 2024. Learn More or Try it out now .

  • Advanced Search
  • Journal List

Logo of plosone

The Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis and Probabilistic Inference: Evidence from the Domain of Color

Emily cibelli.

1 Department of Linguistics, Northwestern University, Evanston, IL 60208, United States of America

2 Department of Linguistics, University of California, Berkeley, CA 94720, United States of America

3 Cognitive Science Program, University of California, Berkeley, CA 94720, United States of America

Joseph L. Austerweil

4 Department of Psychology, University of Wisconsin, Madison, WI 53706, United States of America

Thomas L. Griffiths

5 Department of Psychology, University of California, Berkeley, CA 94720, United States of America

Terry Regier

Conceived and designed the experiments: EC YX JLA TLG TR. Performed the experiments: EC YX JLA. Analyzed the data: EC YX JLA. Wrote the paper: TR EC YX.

Associated Data

All relevant data are available within the paper and/or at: https://github.com/yangxuch/probwhorfcolor This GitHub repository is mentioned in the paper.

The Sapir-Whorf hypothesis holds that our thoughts are shaped by our native language, and that speakers of different languages therefore think differently. This hypothesis is controversial in part because it appears to deny the possibility of a universal groundwork for human cognition, and in part because some findings taken to support it have not reliably replicated. We argue that considering this hypothesis through the lens of probabilistic inference has the potential to resolve both issues, at least with respect to certain prominent findings in the domain of color cognition. We explore a probabilistic model that is grounded in a presumed universal perceptual color space and in language-specific categories over that space. The model predicts that categories will most clearly affect color memory when perceptual information is uncertain. In line with earlier studies, we show that this model accounts for language-consistent biases in color reconstruction from memory in English speakers, modulated by uncertainty. We also show, to our knowledge for the first time, that such a model accounts for influential existing data on cross-language differences in color discrimination from memory, both within and across categories. We suggest that these ideas may help to clarify the debate over the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis.

Introduction

The Sapir-Whorf hypothesis [ 1 , 2 ] holds that our thoughts are shaped by our native language, and that speakers of different languages therefore think about the world in different ways. This proposal has been controversial for at least two reasons, both of which are well-exemplified in the semantic domain of color. The first source of controversy is that the hypothesis appears to undercut any possibility of a universal foundation for human cognition. This idea sits uneasily with the finding that variation in color naming across languages is constrained, such that certain patterns of color naming recur frequently across languages [ 3 – 5 ], suggesting some sort of underlying universal basis. The second source of controversy is that while some findings support the hypothesis, they do not always replicate reliably. Many studies have found that speakers of a given language remember and process color in a manner that reflects the color categories of their language [ 6 – 13 ]. Reinforcing the idea that language is implicated in these findings, it has been shown that the apparent effect of language on color cognition disappears when participants are given a verbal [ 7 ] (but not a visual) interference task [ 8 , 11 , 12 ]; this suggests that language may operate through on-line use of verbal representations that can be temporarily disabled. However, some of these findings have a mixed record of replication [ 14 – 17 ]. Thus, despite the substantial empirical evidence already available, the role of language in color cognition remains disputed.

An existing theoretical stance holds the potential to resolve both sources of controversy. On the one hand, it explains effects of language on cognition in a framework that retains a universal component, building on a proposal by Kay and Kempton [ 7 ]. On the other hand, it has the potential to explain when effects of language on color cognition will appear, and when they will not—and why. This existing stance is that of the “category adjustment” model of Huttenlocher and colleagues [ 18 , 19 ]. We adopt this stance, and cast color memory as inference under uncertainty, instantiated in a category adjustment model, following Bae et al. [ 20 ] and Persaud and Hemmer [ 21 ]. The model holds that color memory involves the probabilistic combination of evidence from two sources: a fine-grained representation of the particular color seen, and the language-specific category in which it fell (e.g. English green ). Both sources of evidence are represented in a universal perceptual color space, yet their combination yields language-specific bias patterns in memory, as illustrated in Fig 1 . The model predicts that such category effects will be strongest when fine-grained perceptual information is uncertain. It thus has the potential to explain the mixed pattern of replications of Whorfian effects in the literature: non-replications could be the result of high perceptual certainty.

An external file that holds a picture, illustration, etc.
Object name is pone.0158725.g001.jpg

A stimulus is encoded in two ways: (1) a fine-grained representation of the stimulus itself, shown as a (gray) distribution over stimulus space centered at the stimulus’ location in that space, and (2) the language-specific category (e.g. English “green”) in which the stimulus falls, shown as a separate (green) distribution over the same space, centered at the category prototype. The stimulus is reconstructed by combining these two sources of information through probabilistic inference, resulting in a reconstruction of the stimulus (black distribution) that is biased toward the category prototype. Adapted from Fig 11 of Bae et al. (2015) [ 20 ].

In the category adjustment model, both the fine-grained representation of the stimulus and the category in which it falls are modeled as probability distributions over a universal perceptual color space. The fine-grained representation is veridical (unbiased) but inexact: its distribution is centered at the location in color space where the stimulus itself fell, and the variance of that distribution captures the observer’s uncertainty about the precise location of the stimulus in color space, with greater variance corresponding to greater uncertainty. Psychologically, such uncertainty might be caused by noise in perception itself, by memory decay over time, or by some other cause—and any increase in such uncertainty is modeled by a wider, flatter distribution for the fine-grained representation. The category distribution, in contrast, captures the information about stimulus location that is given by the named category in which the stimulus fell (e.g. green for an English-speaking observer). Because named color categories vary across languages, this category distribution is assumed to be language-specific—although the space over which it exists is universal. The model infers the original stimulus location by combining evidence from both of these distributions. As a result, the model tends to produce reconstructions of the stimulus that are biased away from the actual location of the stimulus and toward the prototype of the category in which it falls.

As illustrated in Fig 2 , this pattern of bias pulls stimuli on opposite sides of a category boundary in opposite directions, producing enhanced distinctiveness for such stimuli. Such enhanced distinctiveness across a category boundary is the signature of categorical perception, or analogous category effects in memory. On this view, language-specific effects on memory can emerge from a largely universal substrate when one critical component of that substrate is language-specific: the category distribution.

An external file that holds a picture, illustration, etc.
Object name is pone.0158725.g002.jpg

Model reconstructions tend to be biased toward category prototypes, yielding enhanced distinctiveness for two stimuli that fall on different sides of a category boundary. Categories are shown as distributions in green and blue; stimuli are shown as vertical black lines; reconstruction bias patterns are shown as arrows.

If supported, the category adjustment model holds the potential to clarify the debate over the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis in three ways. First, it would link that debate to independent principles of probabilistic inference. In so doing, it would underscore the potentially important role of uncertainty , whether originating in memory or perception, in framing the debate theoretically. Second, and relatedly, it would suggest a possible reason why effects of language on color memory and perception are sometimes found, and sometimes not [ 17 ]. Concretely, the model predicts that greater uncertainty in the fine-grained representation—induced for example through a memory delay, or noise in perception—will lead to greater influence of the category, and thus a stronger bias in reproduction. The mirror-image of this prediction is that in situations of relatively high certainty in memory or perception, there will be little influence of the category, to the point that such an influence may not be empirically detectable. Third, the model suggests a way to think about the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis without jettisoning the important idea of a universal foundation for cognition.

Closely related ideas appear in the literature on probabilistic cue integration [ 22 – 25 ]. For example, Ernst and Banks [ 24 ] investigated perceptual integration of cues from vision and touch in judging the height of an object. They found that humans integrate visual and haptic cues in a statistically optimal fashion, modulated by cue certainty. The category adjustment model we explore here can be seen as a form of probabilistic cue integration in which one of the cues is a language-specific category.

The category adjustment model has been used to account for category effects in various domains, including spatial location [ 18 , 26 ], object size [ 19 , 27 ], and vowel perception [ 28 ]. The category adjustment model also bears similarities to other theoretical accounts of the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis that emphasize the importance of verbal codes [ 7 , 8 ], and the interplay of such codes with perceptual representations [ 29 – 31 ]. Prior research has linked such category effects to probabilistic inference, following the work of Huttenlocher and colleagues [ 18 , 19 ]. Roberson and colleagues [ 32 ] invoked the category adjustment model as a possible explanation for categorical perception of facial expressions, but did not explore a formal computational model; Goldstone [ 33 ] similarly referenced the category adjustment model with respect to category effects in the color domain. Persaud and Hemmer [ 21 , 34 ] explored bias in memory for color, and compared empirically obtained memory bias patterns from English speakers with results predicted by a formally specified category adjustment model, but did not link those results to the debate over the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis, and did not manipulate uncertainty. More recently, a subsequent paper by the same authors and colleagues [ 35 ] explored category-induced bias in speakers of another language, Tsimané, and did situate those results with respect to the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis, but again did not manipulate uncertainty. Most recently, Bae et al. [ 20 ] extensively documented bias in color memory in English speakers, modeled those results with a category-adjustment computational model, and did manipulate uncertainty—but did not explore these ideas relative to the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis, or to data from different languages.

In what follows, we first present data and computational simulations that support the recent finding that color memory in English speakers is well-predicted by a category adjustment model, with the strength of category effects modulated by uncertainty. We then show, to our knowledge for the first time, that a category adjustment model accounts for influential existing cross-language data on color that support the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis.

In this section we provide general descriptions of our analyses and results. Full details are supplied in the section on Materials and Methods.

Study 1: Color reconstruction in English speakers

Our first study tests the core assumptions of the category adjustment model in English speakers. In doing so, it probes questions that were pursued by two studies that appeared recently, after this work had begun. Persaud and Hemmer [ 21 ] and Bae et al. [ 20 ] both showed that English speakers’ memory for a color tends to be biased toward the category prototype of the corresponding English color term, in line with a category adjustment model. Bae et al. [ 20 ] also showed that the amount of such bias increases when subjects must retain the stimulus in memory during a delay period, compared to when there is no such delay, as predicted by the principles of the category adjustment model. In our first study, we consider new evidence from English speakers that tests these questions, prior to considering speakers of different languages in our following studies.

English-speaking participants viewed a set of hues that varied in small steps from dark yellow to purple, with most hues corresponding to some variety of either green or blue. We collected two kinds of data from these participants: bias data and naming data. Bias data were based on participants’ non-linguistic reconstruction of particular colors seen. Specifically, for each hue seen, participants recreated that hue by selecting a color from a color wheel, either while the target was still visible ( Fig 3A : simultaneous condition), or from memory after a short delay ( Fig 3B : delayed condition). We refer to the resulting data as bias data, because we are interested in the extent to which participants’ reconstructions of the stimulus color are biased away from the original target stimulus. Afterwards, the same participants indicated how good an example of English green (as in Fig 3C ) and how good an example of English blue each hue was. We refer to these linguistic data as naming data.

An external file that holds a picture, illustration, etc.
Object name is pone.0158725.g003.jpg

Screenshots of example trials illustrating (A) simultaneous reconstruction, (B) delayed reconstruction, and (C) green goodness rating.

Fig 4 shows both naming and bias data as a function of target hue. The top panel of the figure shows the naming data and also shows Gaussian functions corresponding to the English color terms green and blue that we fitted to the naming data. Bias data were collected for only a subset of the hues for which naming data were collected, and the shaded region in the top panel of Fig 4 shows that subset, relative to the full range of hues for naming data. We collected bias data only in this smaller range because we were interested specifically in bias induced by the two color terms blue and green , and colors outside the shaded region seemed to us to clearly show some influence of neighboring categories such as yellow and purple . The bottom panel of the figure shows the bias data, plotted relative to the prototypes (means) of the fitted Gaussian functions for green and blue . It can be seen that reconstruction bias appears to be stronger in the delayed than in the simultaneous condition, as predicted, and that—especially in the delayed condition—there is an inflection in the bias pattern between the two category prototypes, suggesting that bias may reflect the influence of each of the two categories. The smaller shaded region in this bottom panel denotes the subset of these hues that we subsequently analyzed statistically, and to which we fit models. We reduced the range of considered hues slightly further at this stage, to ensure that the range was well-centered with respect to the two relevant category prototypes, for green and blue , as determined by the naming data.

An external file that holds a picture, illustration, etc.
Object name is pone.0158725.g004.jpg

In both top and bottom panels, the horizontal axis denotes target hue, ranging from yellow on the left to purple on the right. Top panel (naming data): The solid green and blue curves show, for each target hue, the average goodness rating for English green and blue respectively, as a proportion of the maximum rating possible. The dashed green and blue curves show Gaussian functions fitted to the naming goodness data. The dotted vertical lines marked at the bottom with green and blue squares denote the prototypes for green and blue , determined as the means of the green and blue fitted Gaussian functions, respectively. The shaded region in the top panel shows the portion of the spectrum for which bias data were collected. Bottom panel (bias data): Solid curves denote, for each target hue, the average reconstruction bias for that hue, such that positive values denote reconstruction bias toward the purple (here, right) end of the spectrum, and negative values denote reconstruction bias toward the yellow (here, left) end of the spectrum. Units for the vertical axis are the same as for the horizontal axis, which is normalized to length 1.0. The black and red curves show bias under simultaneous and delayed response, respectively. Blue stars at the top of the bottom panel mark hues for which there was a significant difference in the magnitude of bias between simultaneous and delayed conditions. The shaded region in the bottom panel shows the portion of the data that was analyzed statistically, and to which models were fit. In both panels, error bars represent standard error of the mean.

The absolute values (magnitudes) of the bias were analyzed using a 2 (condition: simultaneous vs. delayed) × 15 (hues) repeated measures analysis of variance. This analysis revealed significantly greater bias magnitude in the delayed than in the simultaneous condition. It also revealed that bias magnitude differed significantly as a function of hue, as well as a significant interaction between the factors of hue and condition. The blue stars in Fig 4 denote hues for which the difference in bias magnitude between the simultaneous and delayed conditions reached significance. The finding of greater bias magnitude in the delayed than in the simultaneous condition is consistent with the proposal that uncertainty is an important mediating factor in such category effects, as argued by Bae et al. [ 20 ]. It also suggests that some documented failures to find such category effects could in principle be attributable to high certainty, a possibility that can be explored by manipulating uncertainty.

We wished to test in a more targeted fashion to what extent these data are consistent with a category adjustment model in which a color is reconstructed based in part on English named color categories. To that end, we compared the performance of four models against these data; only one of these models considered both of the relevant English color categories, green and blue . As in Fig 1 , each model contains a fine-grained but inexact representation of the perceived stimulus, and (for most models) a representation of one or more English color categories. Each model predicts the reconstruction of the target stimulus from its fine-grained representation of the target together with any category information. Category information in the model is specified by the naming data. Each model has a single free parameter, corresponding to the uncertainty of the fine-grained representation; this parameter is fit to bias data.

  • The null model is a baseline model that predicts hue reconstruction based only on the fine-grained representation of the stimulus, with no category component.
  • The 1-category (green) model predicts hue reconstruction based on the fine-grained representation of the stimulus, combined with a representation of only the green category, derived from the green naming data.
  • The 1-category (blue) model predicts hue reconstruction based on the fine-grained representation of the stimulus, combined with a representation of only the blue category, derived from the blue naming data.
  • The 2-category model predicts hue reconstruction based on the fine-grained representation of the stimulus, combined with representations of both the green and blue categories.

If reproduction bias reflects probabilistic inference from a fine-grained representation of the stimulus itself, together with any relevant category, we would expect the 2-category model to outperform the others. The other models have access either to no category information at all (null model), or to category information for only one of the two relevant color categories (only one of green and blue ). The 2-category model in contrast combines fine-grained stimulus information with both of the relevant categories ( green and blue ); this model thus corresponds most closely to a full category adjustment model.

Fig 5 redisplays the data from simultaneous and delayed reconstruction, this time with model fits overlaid. The panels in the left column show data from simultaneous reconstruction, fit by each of the four models, and the panels in the right column analogously show data and model fits from delayed reconstruction. Visually, it appears that in the case of delayed reconstruction, the 2-category model fits the data at least qualitatively better than competing models: it shows an inflection in bias as the empirical data do, although not as strongly. For simultaneous reconstruction, the 2-category model fit is also reasonable but visually not as clearly superior to the others (especially the null model) as in the delayed condition.

An external file that holds a picture, illustration, etc.
Object name is pone.0158725.g005.jpg

Left column: Bias from simultaneous reconstruction, fit by each of the four models. The empirical data (black lines with error bars) in these four panels are the same, and only the model fits (red lines) differ. Within each panel, the horizontal axis denotes target hue, and the vertical axis denotes reconstruction bias. The green and blue prototypes are indicated as vertical lines with green and blue squares at the bottom. Right column: delayed reconstruction, displayed analogously.

Table 1 reports quantitative results of these model fits. The best fit is provided by the 2-category model, in both the simultaneous and delayed conditions, whether assessed by log likelihood (LL) or by mean squared errror (MSE). In line with earlier studies [ 20 , 21 ], these findings demonstrate that a category adjustment model that assumes stimulus reconstruction is governed by relevant English color terms provides a reasonable fit to data on color reconstruction by English speakers. The category adjustment model fits well both when the category bias is relatively slight (simultaneous condition), and when the bias is stronger (delayed condition).

LL = log likelihood (higher is better). MSE = mean squared error (lower is better). The best value in each row is shown in bold .

MeasureNull1-cat. (G)1-cat. (B)2-cat.
SimultaneousLL253022902510
MSE0.000110.000570.00015
DelayedLL186016501900
MSE0.000990.001600.00061

Study 2: Color discrimination across languages

The study above examined the categories of just one language, English, whereas the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis concerns cross-language differences in categorization, and their effect on cognition and perception. Empirical work concerning this hypothesis has not specifically emphasized bias in reconstruction, but there is a substantial amount of cross-language data of other sorts against which the category adjustment model can be assessed. One method that has been extensively used to explore the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis in the domain of color is a two-alternative forced choice (2AFC) task. In such a task, participants first are briefly shown a target color, and then shortly afterward are shown that same target color together with a different distractor color, and are asked to indicate which was the color originally seen. A general finding from such studies [ 8 – 10 ] is that participants exhibit enhanced discrimination for pairs of colors that would be named differently in their native language. For example, in such a 2AFC task, speakers of English show enhanced discrimination for colors from the different English categories green and blue , compared with colors from the same category (either both green or both blue ) [ 8 ]. In contrast, speakers of the Berinmo language, which has named color categories that differ from those of English, show enhanced discrimination across Berinmo category boundaries, and not across those of English [ 9 ]. Thus color discrimination in this task is enhanced at the boundaries of native language categories, suggesting an effect of those native language categories on the ability to discriminate colors from memory.

Considered informally, this qualitative pattern of results appears to be consistent with the category adjustment model, as suggested above in Fig 2 . We wished to determine whether such a model would also provide a good quantitative account of such results, when assessed using the specific color stimuli and native-language naming patterns considered in the empirical studies just referenced.

We considered cross-language results from two previous studies by Debi Roberson and colleagues, one that compared color memory in speakers of English and Berinmo, a language of Papua New Guinea [ 9 ], and another that explored color memory in speakers of Himba, a language of Namibia [ 10 ]. Berinmo and Himba each have five basic color terms, in contrast with eleven in English. The Berinmo and Himba color category systems are similar to each other in broad outline, but nonetheless differ noticeably. Following these two previous studies, we considered the following pairs of categories in these three languages:

  • the English categories green and blue ,
  • the Berinmo categories wor (covering roughly yellow, orange, and brown), and nol (covering roughly green, blue, and purple), and
  • the Himba categories dumbu (covering roughly yellow and beige) and burou (covering roughly green, blue, and purple).

These three pairs of categories are illustrated in Fig 6 , using naming data from Roberson et al. (2000) [ 9 ] and Roberson et al. (2005) [ 10 ]. It can be seen that the English green - blue distinction is quite different from the Berinmo wor - nol and the Himba dumbu - burou distinctions, which are similar but not identical to each other. The shaded regions in this figure indicate specific colors that were probed in discrimination tasks. The shaded (probed) region that straddles a category boundary in Berinmo and Himba falls entirely within the English category green , and the shaded (probed) region that straddles a category boundary in English falls entirely within the Berinmo category nol and the Himba category burou , according to naming data in Fig 1 of Roberson et al. (2005) [ 10 ]. The empirical discrimination data in Fig 7 are based on those probed colors [ 9 , 10 ], and show that in general, speakers of a language tend to exhibit greater discrimination for pairs of colors that cross a category boundary in their native language, consistent with the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis.

An external file that holds a picture, illustration, etc.
Object name is pone.0158725.g006.jpg

The English categories green and blue (top panel), the Berinmo categories wor and nol (middle panel), and the Himba categories dumbu and burou (bottom panel), plotted against a spectrum of hues that ranges from dark yellow at the left, through green, to blue at the right. Colored squares mark prototypes: the shared prototype for Berinmo wor and Himba dumbu , and the prototypes for English green and blue ; the color of each square approximates the color of the corresponding prototype. For each language, the dotted-and-dashed vertical lines denote the prototypes for the two categories from that language, and the dashed vertical line denotes the empirical boundary between these two categories. Black curves show the probability of assigning a given hue to each of the two native-language categories, according to the category component of a 2-category model fit to each language’s naming data. The shaded regions mark the ranges of colors probed in discrimination tasks; these two regions are centered at the English green - blue boundary and the Berinmo wor - nol boundary. Data are from Roberson et al. (2000) [ 9 ] and Roberson et al. (2005) [ 10 ].

An external file that holds a picture, illustration, etc.
Object name is pone.0158725.g007.jpg

Top panels: Discrimination from memory by Berinmo and English speakers for pairs of colors across and within English and Berinmo color category boundaries. Empirical data are from Table 11 of Roberson et al. (2000:392). Empirical values show mean proportion correct 2AFC memory judgments, and error bars show standard error. Model values show mean model proportion correct 2AFC memory judgments after simulated reconstruction with native-language categories. Model results are range-matched to the corresponding empirical values, such that the minimum and maximum model values match the minimum and maximum mean values in the corresponding empirical dataset, and other model values are linearly interpolated. Bottom panels: Discrimination from memory by Himba and English speakers for pairs of colors across and within English and Himba color category boundaries, compared with model results based on native-language categories. Empirical data are from Table 6 of Roberson et al. (2005:400); no error bars are shown because standard error was not reported in that table.

We sought to determine whether the 2-category model explored above could account for these data. To that end, for each language, we created a version of the 2-category model based on the naming data for that language. Thus, we created an English model in which the two categories were based on empirical naming data for green and blue , a Berinmo model in which the two categories were based on empirical naming data for wor and nol , and a Himba model in which the two categories were based on empirical naming data for dumbu and burou . The black curves in Fig 6 show the probability of assigning a given hue to each of the two native-language categories, according to the category component of a 2-category model fit to each language’s naming data. Given this category information, we simulated color reconstruction from memory for the specific colors considered in the empirical studies [ 9 , 10 ] (the colors in the shaded regions in Fig 6 ). We did so separately for the cases of English, Berinmo, and Himba, in each case fitting a model based on naming data for a given language to discrimination data from speakers of that language. As in Study 1, we fit the model parameter corresponding to the uncertainty of fine-grained perceptual representation to the empirical non-linguistic (here discrimination) data, and we used a single value for this parameter across all three language models. The model results are shown in Fig 7 , beside the empirical data to which they were fit. The models provide a reasonable match to the observed cross-language differences in discrimination. Specifically, the stimulus pairs for which empirical performance is best are those that cross a native-language boundary—and these are stimulus pairs for which the corresponding model response is strongest.

Although not shown in the figure, we also conducted a followup analysis to test whether the quality of these fits was attributable merely to model flexibility, or to a genuine fit between a language’s category system and patterns of discrimination from speakers of that language. We did this by switching which language’s model was fit to which language’s discrimination data. Specifically, we fit the model based on Berinmo naming to the discrimination data from English speakers (and vice versa), and fit the model based on Himba naming to the discrimination data from English speakers (and vice versa), again adjusting the model parameter corresponding to the uncertainty of the fine-grained perceptual representation to the empirical discrimination data. The results are summarized in Table 2 . It can be seen that the discrimination data are fit better by native-language models (that is, models with a category component originally fit to that language’s naming data) than by other-language models (that is, models with a category component originally fit to another language’s naming data). These results suggest that cross-language differences in discrimination may result from category-induced reconstruction bias under uncertainty, guided by native-language categories.

The best value in each row is shown in bold . Data are fit better by native-language models than by other-language models.

Berinmo-English comparison
Berinmo modelEnglish model
Berinmo discrimination data 0.0080
English discrimination data0.0019
Himba-English comparison
Himba modelEnglish model
Himba discrimination data 0.0039
English discrimination data0.0029

Study 3: Within-category effects

Although many studies of categorical perception focus on pairs of stimuli that cross category boundaries, there is also evidence for category effects within categories. In a 2AFC study of categorical perception of facial expressions, Roberson and colleagues [ 32 ] found the behavioral signature of categorical perception (or more precisely in this case, categorical memory): superior discrimination for cross-category than for within-category pairs of stimuli. But in addition, they found an interesting category effect on within-category pairs, dependent on order of presentation. For each within-category pair they considered, one stimulus of the pair was always closer to the category prototype (the “good exemplar”) than the other (the “poor exemplar”). They found that 2AFC performance on within-category pairs was better when the target was the good exemplar (and the distractor was therefore the poor exemplar) than when the target was the poor exemplar (and the distractor was therefore the good exemplar)—even though the same stimuli were involved in the two cases. Moreover, performance in the former (good exemplar) case did not differ significantly from cross-category performance. Hanley and Roberson [ 36 ] subsequently reanalyzed data from a number of earlier studies that had used 2AFC tasks to explore cross-language differences in color naming and cognition, including those reviewed and modeled in the previous section. Across studies and across domains, including color, they found the same asymmetrical within-category effect originally documented for facial expressions.

This within-category pattern may be naturally explained in category-adjustment terms, as shown in Fig 8 , and as argued by Roberson and colleagues [ 32 ]. The central idea is that because the target is held in memory, it is subject to bias toward the prototype in memory, making discrimination of target from distractor either easier or harder depending on which of the two stimuli is the target. Although this connection with the category adjustment model has been made in the literature in general conceptual terms [ 32 ], followup studies have been theoretically focused elsewhere [ 31 , 36 ], and the idea has not to our knowledge been tested computationally using the specific stimuli and naming patterns involved in the empirical studies. We sought to do so.

An external file that holds a picture, illustration, etc.
Object name is pone.0158725.g008.jpg

The category adjustment model predicts: (top panel, good exemplar) easy within-category discrimination in a 2AFC task when the initially-presented target t is closer to the prototype than the distractor d is; (bottom panel, poor exemplar) difficult within-category discrimination with the same two stimuli when the initially-presented target t is farther from the prototype than the distractor d is. Category is shown as a distribution in blue; stimuli are shown as vertical black lines marked t and d; reconstruction bias patterns are shown as arrows.

The empirical data in Fig 9 illustrate the within-category effect with published results on color discrimination by speakers of English, Berinmo, and Himba. In attempting to account for these data, we considered again the English, Berinmo, and Himba variants of the 2-category model first used in Study 2, and also retained from that study the parameter value corresponding to the uncertainty of the fine-grained perceptual representation, in the case of native-language models. We simulated reconstruction from memory of the specific colors examined in Study 2. Following the empirical analyses, this time we disaggregated the within-category stimulus pairs into those in which the target was a good exemplar of the category (i.e. the target was closer to the prototype than the distractor was), vs. those in which the target was a poor exemplar of the category (i.e. the target was farther from the prototype than the distractor was). The model results are shown in Fig 9 , and match the empirical data reasonably well, supporting the informal in-principle argument of Fig 8 with a more detailed quantitative analysis.

An external file that holds a picture, illustration, etc.
Object name is pone.0158725.g009.jpg

Across: stimulus pair crosses the native-language boundary; GE: within-category pair, target is the good exemplar; PE: within-category pair, target is the poor exemplar. Empirical data are from Figs 2 (English: 10-second retention interval), 3 (Berinmo), and 4 (Himba) of Hanley and Roberson [ 36 ]. Empirical values show mean proportion correct 2AFC memory judgments, and error bars show standard error. Model values show mean model proportion correct 2AFC memory judgments after simulated reconstruction using native-language categories, range-matched as in Fig 7 . English model compared with English data: 0.00002 MSE; Berinmo model compared with Berinmo data: 0.00055 MSE; Himba model compared with Himba data: 0.00087 MSE.

Conclusions

We have argued that the debate over the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis may be clarified by viewing that hypothesis in terms of probabilistic inference. To that end, we have presented a probabilistic model of color memory, building on proposals in the literature. The model assumes both a universal color space and language-specific categorical partitionings of that space, and infers the originally perceived color from these two sources of evidence. The structure of this model maps naturally onto a prominent proposal in the literature that has to our knowledge not previously been formalized in these terms. In a classic early study of the effect of language on color cognition, Kay and Kempton [ 7 ] interpret Whorf [ 2 ] as follows:

Whorf […] suggests that he conceives of experience as having two tiers: one, a kind of rock bottom, inescapable seeing-things-as-they-are (or at least as human beings cannot help but see them), and a second, in which [the specific structures of a given language] cause us to classify things in ways that could be otherwise (and are otherwise for speakers of a different language).

Kay and Kempton argue that color cognition involves an interaction between these two tiers. The existence of a universal groundwork for color cognition helps to explain why there are constraints on color naming systems across languages [ 3 – 5 , 37 ]. At the same time, Kay and Kempton acknowledge a role for the language-specific tier in cognition, such that “there do appear to be incursions of linguistic categorization into apparently nonlinguistic processes of thinking” (p. 77). These two tiers map naturally onto the universal and language-specific components of the model we have explored here. This structure offers a straightforward way to think about effects of language on cognition while retaining the idea of a universal foundation underpinning human perception and cognition. Thus, this general approach, and our model as an instance of it, offer a possible resolution of one source of controversy surrounding the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis: taking that hypothesis seriously need not entail a wholesale rejection of important universal components of human cognition.

The approach proposed here also has the potential to resolve another source of controversy surrounding the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis: that some findings taken to support it do not replicate reliably (e.g. in the case of color: [ 15 – 17 ]). Framing the issue in terms of probabilistic inference touches this question by highlighting the theoretically central role of uncertainty , as in models of probabilistic cue integration [ 24 ]. We have seen stronger category-induced bias in color memory under conditions of greater delay and presumably therefore greater uncertainty (Study 1, and [ 20 ]). This suggests that in the inverse case of high certainty about the stimulus, any category effect could in principle be so small as to be empirically undetectable, a possibility that can be pursued by systematically manipulating uncertainty. Thus, the account advanced here casts the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis in formal terms that suggest targeted and quantitative followup tests. A related theoretical advantage of uncertainty is that it highlights an important level of generality: uncertainty could result from memory, as explored here, but it could also result from noise or ambiguity in perception itself, and on the view advanced here, the result should be the same.

The model we have proposed does not cover all aspects of language effects on color cognition. For example, there are documented priming effects [ 31 ] which do not appear to flow as naturally from this account as do the other effects we have explored above. However, the model does bring together disparate bodies of data in a simple framework, and links them to independent principles of probabilistic inference. Future research can usefully probe the generality and the limitations of the ideas we have explored here.

Materials and Methods

Code and data supporting the analyses reported here are available at https://github.com/yangxuch/probwhorfcolor.git .

The basic model we consider is shown in Fig 10 , which presents in graphical form the generative process behind Fig 1 above. Our model follows in general outline that of Bae et al. [ 20 ], but the formalization of inference within this structure more closely follows Feldman et al.’s [ 28 ] model of category effects in vowel perception. In our model, the perception of a stimulus S = s produces a fine-grained memory M , and a categorical code c . We wish to obtain a reconstruction s ^ of the original stimulus S = s , by combining evidence from the two internal representations M and c that s has produced. That reconstruction is derived as follows:

Because hue is a circular dimension, the components p ( M | S ) and p ( S | c ) could be modeled using circular normal or von Mises distributions, as was done by Bae et al. [ 20 ]. However each of our studies treats only a restricted subsection of the full hue circle, and for that reason we instead model these representations using normal distributions.

An external file that holds a picture, illustration, etc.
Object name is pone.0158725.g010.jpg

The perception of stimulus S = s produces a fine-grained memory M , and a categorical code c specifying the category in which s fell. We wish to reconstruct the original stimulus S = s , given M and c .

p ( M | S ) represents the fine-grained memory trace M of the original stimulus S = s . We model this as a normal distribution with mean μ m at the location of the original stimulus s , and with uncertainty captured by variance σ m 2 :

This is an unbiased representation of the original stimulus s because μ m = s .

p ( S | c ) captures the information about the location of stimulus S that is given by the categorical code c . We again model this as a normal distribution, this time centered at the prototype μ c of category c , with variance σ c 2 :

This assumes that there is a single categorical code c , and we use this assumption in some of our model variants below. However in other cases we will capture the fact that more than one category may be applicable to a stimulus. In such cases we assume that the perceiver knows, for each category c , the applicability π ( c ) of that category for the observed stimulus s . We model this as:

where p ( S = s | c ) is given by Eq (4) above, and p ( c ) is assumed to be uniform.

We consider three variants of this basic model, described below in order of increasing complexity: the null model, the 1-category model, and the 2-category model. For each model, we take the predicted reconstruction s ^ of a given stimulus S = s to be the expected value of the posterior distribution:

The null model assumes that reconstruction is based only on the fine-grained memory, with no category influence. This model is derived from Eq (2) by assuming that the memory component p ( M | S ) is as defined above, and the category component p ( S | c ) is uniform, yielding:

The predicted reconstruction for this model is given by the expected value of this distribution, namely:

where we have assumed μ m = s , the originally observed stimulus. This model predicts no category-induced bias: the reconstruction of the stimulus S = s is simply the value of the stimulus s itself.

1-category model

The 1-category model assumes that reconstruction is based both on fine-grained memory and on information from a single category, e.g. English green . This model is derived from Eq (2) by assuming that both the memory component p ( M | S ) and the category component p ( S | c ) are as defined above, yielding:

where we have assumed μ m = s , the originally observed stimulus. This equation parallels Eq (7) of Feldman et al. [ 28 ]. This model produces a reconstruction that is a weighted average of the original stimulus value s and the category prototype μ c , with weights determined by the relative certainty of each of the two sources of information. The same weighted average is also central to Ernst and Banks’ [ 24 ] study of cue integration from visual and haptic modalities. That study was based on the same principles we invoke here, and our model—like that of Feldman et al.—can be viewed as a probabilistic cue integration model in which one of the two cues being integrated is a category, rather than a cue from a different modality.

2-category model

The 2-category model is similar to the 1-category model, but instead of basing its reconstruction on a single category c , it bases its reconstruction on two categories c 1 and c 2 (e.g. English green and blue ). It does so by averaging together the reconstruction provided by the 1-category model for c 1 and the reconstruction provided by the 1-category model for c 2 , weighted by the applicability π ( c ) of each category c to the stimulus:

Here, p ( S | M , c ) inside the sum is given by the 1-category model specified in Eq (9) , and π ( c ) is the applicability of category c to the observed stimulus s as specified above in Eq (5) . Our equation here parallels Eq (9) of Feldman et al. [ 28 ] who similarly take a weighted average over 1-category models in their model of category effects in speech perception. The predicted reconstruction for this model is given by the expected value of this distribution, namely:

assuming as before that μ m = s , the original stimulus value. This equation follows Feldman et al. [ 28 ] Eq (10).

Fitting models to data

For each model, any category parameters μ c and σ c 2 are first fit to naming data. The single remaining free parameter σ m 2 , corresponding to the uncertainty of fine-grained memory, is then fit to non-linguistic bias or discrimination data, with no further adjustment of the category parameters. Although this two-step process is used in all of our studies, it is conducted in slightly different ways across studies; we supply study-specific details below in our presentation of each study. All model fits were done using fminsearch in Matlab.

Participants

Twenty subjects participated in the experiment, having been recruited at UC Berkeley. All subjects were at least 18 years of age, native English speakers, and reported normal or corrected-to-normal vision, and no colorblindness. All subjects received payment or course credit for participation.

Informed consent was obtained verbally; all subjects read an approved consent form and verbally acknowledged their willingness to participate in the study. Verbal consent was chosen because the primary risk to subjects in this study was for their names to be associated with their response; this approach allowed us to obtain consent and collect data without the need to store subjects’ names in any form. Once subjects acknowledged that they understood the procedures and agreed to participate by stating so to the experimenter, the experimenter recorded their consent by assigning them a subject number, which was anonymously linked to their data. All study procedures, including those involving consent, were overseen and approved by the UC Berkeley Committee for the Protection of Human Subjects.

Stimuli were selected by varying a set of hues centered around the blue - green boundary, holding saturation and lightness constant. Stimuli were defined in Munsell coordinate space, which is widely used in the literature we engage here (e.g. [ 9 , 10 ]). All stimuli were at lightness 6 and saturation 8. Hue varied from 5Y to 10P, in equal hue steps of 2.5. Colors were converted to xyY coordinate space following Table I(6.6.1) of Wyszecki and Stiles (1982) [ 38 ]. The colors were implemented in Matlab in xyY; the correspondence of these coordinate systems in the stimulus set, as well as approximate visualizations of the stimuli, are reported in Table 3 .

All stimuli were presented at lightness 6, saturation 8 in Munsell space.

Munsell huexyY coordinatesStimulus
15Y0.4426, 0.4588, 30.05
27.5Y0.4321, 0.4719, 30.05
310Y0.4201, 0.4812, 30.05
42.5GY0.4006, 0.4885, 30.05
55GY0.3772, 0.4880, 30.05
67.5GY0.3418, 0.4768, 30.05
710GY0.3116, 0.4563, 30.05
82.5G0.2799, 0.4239, 30.05
95G0.2612, 0.3990, 30.05
107.5G0.2510, 0.3829, 30.05
1110G0.2420, 0.3679, 30.05
122.5BG0.2332, 0.3522, 30.05
135BG0.2236, 0.3311, 30.05
147.5BG0.2171, 0.3138, 30.05
1510BG0.2116, 0.2950, 30.05
162.5B0.2080, 0.2789, 30.05
175B0.2088, 0.2635, 30.05
187.5B0.2132, 0.2537, 30.05
1910B0.2189, 0.2468, 30.05
202.5PB0.2274, 0.2406, 30.05
215PB0.2360, 0.2365, 30.05
227.5PB0.2505, 0.2347, 30.05
2310PB0.2637, 0.2352, 30.05
242.5P0.2770, 0.2372, 30.05
255P0.2905, 0.2421, 30.05
267.5P0.3099, 0.2502, 30.05
2710P0.3259, 0.2584, 30.05

We considered three progressively narrower ranges of these stimuli for different aspects of our analyses, in an attempt to focus the analyses on a region that is well-centered relative to the English color categories green and blue . We refer to these three progressively narrower ranges as the full range , the medium range , and the focused range . We specify these ranges below, together with the aspects of the analysis for which each was used.

  • Full range: We collected naming data for green and blue relative to the full range, stimuli 1-27, for a total of 27 stimuli. We fit the category components of our models to naming data over this full range.
  • Medium range: We collected bias data for a subset of the full range, namely the medium range, stimuli 5-23, for a total of 19 stimuli. We considered this subset because we were interested in bias induced by the English color terms green and blue , and we had the impression, prior to collecting naming or bias data, that colors outside this medium range had some substantial element of the neighboring categories yellow and purple .
  • Focused range: Once we had naming data, we narrowed the range further based on those data, to the focused range, stimuli 5-19, for a total of 15 stimuli. The focused range extends between the (now empirically assessed) prototypes for green and blue , and also includes three of our stimulus hues on either side of these prototypes, yielding a range well-centered relative to those prototypes, as can be seen in the bottom panel of Fig 4 above. We considered this range in our statistical analyses, and in our modeling of bias patterns.

Experimental procedure

The experiment consisted of four blocks. The first two blocks were reconstruction (bias) tasks: one simultaneous block and one delay block. In the simultaneous block ( Fig 3A ), the subject was shown a stimulus color as a colored square (labeled as “Original” in the figure), and was asked to recreate that color in a second colored square (labeled as “Target” in the figure) as accurately as possible by selecting a hue from a color wheel. The (“Original”) stimulus color remained on screen while the subject selected a response from the color wheel; navigation of the color wheel would change the color of the response (“Target”) square. The stimulus square and response square each covered 4.5 degrees of visual angle, and the color wheel covered 11.1 degrees of visual angle. Target colors were drawn from the medium range of stimuli (stimuli 5—23 of Table 3 ). The color wheel was constructed based on the full range of stimuli (stimuli 1—27 of Table 3 ), supplemented by interpolating 25 points evenly in xyY coordinates between each neighboring pair of the 27 stimuli of the full range, to create a finely discretized continuum from yellow to purple, with 677 possible responses. Each of the 19 target colors of the medium range was presented five times per block in random order, for a total of 95 trials per block. The delay block ( Fig 3B ) was similar to the simultaneous block but with the difference that the stimulus color was shown for 500 milliseconds then disappeared, then a fixation cross was shown for 1000 milliseconds, after which the subject was asked to reconstruct the target color from memory, again using the color wheel to change the color of the response square. The one colored square shown in the final frame of Fig 3B is the response square that changed color under participant control. The order of the simultaneous block and delay block were counterbalanced by subject. Trials were presented with a 500 millisecond inter-trial interval.

Several steps were taken to ensure that responses made on the color wheel during the reconstruction blocks were not influenced by bias towards a particular spatial position. The position of the color wheel was randomly rotated up to 180 degrees from trial to trial. The starting position of the cursor was likewise randomly generated for each new trial. Finally, the extent of the spectrum was jittered one or two stimuli (2.5 or 5 hue steps) from trial to trial, which had the effect of shifting the spectrum slightly in the yellow or the purple direction from trial to trial. This was done to ensure that the blue - green boundary would not fall at a consistent distance from the spectrum endpoints on each trial.

The second two blocks were naming tasks. In each, subjects were shown each of the 27 stimuli of the full range five times in random order, for a total of 135 trials per block. On each trial, subjects were asked to rate how good an example of a given color name each stimulus was. In one block, the color name was green , in the other, the color name was blue ; order of blocks was counterbalanced by subject. To respond, subjects positioned a slider bar with endpoints “Not at all [green/blue]” and “Perfectly [green/blue]” to the desired position matching their judgment of each stimulus, as shown above in Fig 3C . Responses in the naming blocks were self-paced. Naming blocks always followed reconstruction blocks, to ensure that repeated exposure to the color terms green and blue did not bias responses during reconstruction.

The experiment was presented in Matlab version 7.11.0 (R2010b) using Psychtoolbox (version 3) [ 39 – 41 ]. The experiment was conducted in a dark, sound-attenuated booth on an LCD monitor that supported 24-bit color. The monitor had been characterized using a Minolta CS100 colorimeter. A chin rest was used to ensure that each subject viewed the screen from a constant position; when in position, the base of the subject’s chin was situated 30 cm from the screen.

As part of debriefing after testing was complete, each subject was asked to report any strategies they used during the delay block to help them remember the target color. Summaries of each response, as reported by the experimenter, are listed in Table 4 .

When subjects gave specific examples of color terms used as memory aids, they are reported here.

SubjectDebriefing: strategy during delay block
1Used two-color words (e.g. ‘blue-green’) to help remember target.
2Said the name of the color (e.g. ‘periwinkle’, ‘yellow-green’) during some delays.
3Visualized color during delays.
4Used verbal cues.
5Used verbal cues (‘blueish’, ‘green’, etc.).
6Used labels (e.g. ‘forest green’), but reported feeling that it did not help much.
7Tried to relate each target to something in nature (e.g. ‘grass green’).
8Tried to use words (e.g. ‘seafoam’, ‘forest green’, ‘mauve’, etc.).
9For first 10 trials, used the labels ‘teal’, ‘grass green’, and ‘purple’ as bases, and modified to the specific target (e.g. ‘greener teal’). Subject reported finding this initial system too difficult, and just tried to picture the color in subsequent trials.
10Associated each target with word (e.g. ‘violet’, ‘olive green’, ‘forest green’).
11Mentally pictured target color.
12Named color (e.g. ‘teal’, ‘turquoise’) and what “scheme” (e.g. ‘orange’) it was. Sometimes used a comparison to the previous trial (“a little more orange than previous target”, etc.).
13Named general color (e.g. ‘blue’, ‘green’), and then pictured what shade it was.
14Subject reported using no strategy other than mentally visualizing the color.
15Subject reported visualizing the color and taking a mental snapshot of it.
16Picked color that was closest to what was seen and graded degree to which it was similar (e.g. ‘lighter’, ‘darker’).
17Mentally described target color (e.g. ‘sky blue’, ‘olive green’).
18Used verbal descriptors for color (e.g. ‘aquamarine’, ‘olive green’).
19Named color and gave mental description (e.g. ‘teal’).
20No specific strategy reported.

Color spectrum

We wished to consider our stimuli along a 1-dimensional spectrum such that distance between two colors on that spectrum approximates the perceptual difference between those colors. To this end, we first converted our stimuli to CIELAB color space. CIELAB is a 3-dimensional color space designed “in an attempt to provide coordinates for colored stimuli so that the distance between the coordinates of any two stimuli is predictive of the perceived color difference between them” (p. 202 of [ 42 ]). The conversion to CIELAB was done according to the equations on pp. 167-168 of Wyszecki and Stiles (1982) [ 38 ], assuming 2 degree observer and D65 illuminant. For each pair of neighboring colors in the set of 677 colors of our color wheel, we measured the distance (Δ E ) betwen these two colors in CIELAB space. We then arranged all colors along a 1-dimensional spectrum that was scaled to length 1, such that the distance between each pair of neighboring colors along that spectrum was proportional to the CIELAB Δ E distance between them. This CIELAB-based 1-dimensional spectrum was used for our analyses in Study 1, and an analogous spectrum for a different set of colors was used for our analyses in Studies 2 and 3.

Statistical analysis

As a result of the experiment detailed above, we obtained bias data from 20 participants, for each of 19 hues (the medium range), for 5 trials per hue per participant, in each of the simultaneous and delayed conditions. For analysis purposes, we restricted attention to the focused range of stimuli (15 hues), in order to consider a region of the spectrum that is well-centered with respect to green and blue , as we are primarily interested in bias that may be induced by these two categories. We wished to determine whether the magnitude of the bias differed as a function of the simultaneous vs. delayed condition, whether the magnitude of the bias varied as a function of hue, and whether there was an interaction between these two factors. To answer those questions, we conducted a 2 (condition: simultaneous vs. delayed) × 15 (hues) repeated measures analysis of variance (ANOVA), in which the dependent measure was the absolute value of the reproduction bias (reproduced hue minus target hue), averaged across trials for a given participant at a given target hue in a given condition. The ANOVA included an error term to account for across-subject variability. We found a main effect of condition, with greater bias magnitude in the delayed than in the simultaneous condition [ F (1, 19) = 61.61, p < 0.0001], a main effect of hue [ F (14, 266) = 4.565, p < 0.0001], and an interaction of hue and condition [ F (14, 266) = 3.763, p < 0.0001]. All hue calculations were relative to the CIELAB-based spectrum detailed in the preceding section.

We then conducted paired t-tests at each of the target hues, comparing each participant’s bias magnitude for that hue (averaged over trials) in the simultaneous condition vs. the delayed condition. Blue asterisks at the top of Fig 4 mark hues for which the paired t-test returned p < 0.05 when applying Bonferroni corrections for multiple comparisons.

Modeling procedure

We considered four models in accounting for color reconstruction in English speakers: the null model, a 1-category model for which the category was green , a 1-category model for which the category was blue , and a 2-category model based on both green and blue .

We fit these models to the data in two steps. We first fit any category parameters (the means μ c and variances σ c 2 for any categories c ) to the naming data. We then fit the one remaining free parameter ( σ m 2 ), which captures the uncertainty of fine-grained memory, to the bias data, without further adjusting the category parameters. We specify each of these two steps below.

We fit a Gaussian function to the goodness naming data for green , and another Gaussian function to the data for blue , using maximum likelihood estimation. The fitted Gaussian functions can be seen, together with the data to which they were fit, in the top panel of Fig 4 . This process determined values for the category means μ c and category variances σ c 2 for the two categories green and blue .

For each of the four variants of the category adjustment model outlined above (null, 1-category green, 1-category blue, and 2-category), we retained the category parameter settings resulting from the above fit to the naming data. We then obtained a value for the one remaining free parameter σ m 2 , corresponding to the uncertainty of fine-grained memory, by fitting the model to the bias data via maximum likelihood estimation, without further adjusting the category parameters.

Empirical data

The empirical data considered for this study were drawn from two sources: the study of 2AFC color discrimination by speakers of Berinmo and English in Experiment 6a of Roberson et al. (2000) [ 9 ], and the study of 2AFC color discrimination by speakers of Himba and English in Experiment 3b of Roberson et al. (2005) [ 10 ]. In both studies, two sets of color stimuli were considered, all at value (lightness) level 5, and chroma (saturation) level 8. Both sets varied in hue by increments of 2.5 Munsell hue steps. The first set of stimuli was centered at the English green - blue boundary (hue 7.5BG), and contained the following seven hues: 10G, 2.5BG, 5BG, 7.5BG, 10BG, 2.5B, 5B. The second set of stimuli was centered at the Berinmo wor - nol boundary (hue 5GY), and contained the following seven hues: 7.5Y, 10Y, 2.5GY, 5GY, 7.5GY, 10GY, 2.5G. Stimuli in the set that crossed an English category boundary all fell within a single category in Berinmo ( nol ) and in Himba ( burou ), and stimuli in the set that crossed a Berinmo category boundary also crossed a Himba category boundary ( dumbu - burou ) but all fell within a single category in English ( green ), according to naming data in Fig 1 of Roberson et al. (2005) [ 10 ]. Based on specifications in the original empirical studies [ 9 , 10 ], we took the pairs of stimuli probed to be those presented in Table 5 .

Any stimulus pair that includes a boundary color is considered to be a cross-category pair. All hues are at value (lightness) level 5, and chroma (saturation) level 8. 1s denotes a 1-step pair; 2s denotes a 2-step pair.

English - stimuli (boundary color = 7.5BG)
withinacross
5B-2.5B (1s)7.5BG-5BG (1s)
5B-10BG (2s)2.5B-7.5BG (2s)
5BG-2.5BG (1s)10BG-7.5BG (1s)
5BG-10G (2s)10BG-5BG (2s)
Berinmo - stimuli (boundary color = 5GY)
withinacross
7.5Y-10Y (1s)5GY-7.5GY (1s)
7.5Y-2.5GY (2s)10Y-5GY (2s)
7.5GY-10GY (1s)2.5GY-5GY (1s)
7.5GY-2.5G (2s)2.5GY-7.5GY (2s)
Himba - stimuli (boundary color = 7.5GY)
withinacross
7.5Y-10Y (1s)5GY-7.5GY (1s)
7.5Y-2.5GY (2s)2.5GY-7.5GY (2s)
2.5GY-5GY (1s)7.5GY-10GY (1s)
10Y-5GY (2s)7.5GY-2.5G (2s)

Based on naming data in Fig 1 of Roberson et al. 2005 [ 10 ], we took the prototypes of the relevant color terms to be:

English green prototype = 10GY
English blue prototype = 10B
Berinmo wor prototype = 5Y
Berinmo nol prototype = 5G
Himba dumbu prototype = 5Y
Himba burou prototype = 10G

Fig 6 above shows a spectrum of hues ranging from the Berinmo wor prototype (5Y) to the English blue prototype (10B) in increments of 2.5 Munsell hue steps, categorized according to each of the three languages we consider here. These Munsell hues were converted to xyY and then to CIELAB as above, and the positions of the hues on the spectrum were adjusted so that the distance between each two neighboring hues in the spectrum is proportional to the CIELAB Δ E distance between them. We use this CIELAB-based spectrum for our analyses below. The two shaded regions on each spectrum in Fig 6 denote the two target sets of stimuli identified above.

The discrimination data we modeled were drawn from Table 11 of Roberson et al. (2000:392) [ 9 ] and Table 6 of Roberson et al. (2005:400) [ 10 ].

We considered three variants of the 2-category model: an English blue - green model, a Berinmo wor - nol model, and a Himba dumbu - burou model. As in Study 1, we fit each model to the data in two steps. For each language’s model, we first fit the category component of that model to naming data from that language. Because color naming differs across these languages, this resulted in three models with different category components. For each model, we then retained and fixed the resulting category parameter settings, and fit the single remaining parameter, corresponding to memory uncertainty, to discrimination data. We detail these two steps below.

For the naming data, we modeled the probability of applying category name c to stimulus i as:

where p ( c ) is assumed to be uniform, and f ( i | c ) is a non-normalized Gaussian function corresponding to category c , with mean μ c and variance σ c 2 . There were two categories c for each model, e.g. wor and nol in the case of the Berinmo model. Category means μ c were set to the corresponding category prototypes shown above (e.g. μ c for Berinmo nol corresponded to 5G), and category variances σ c 2 were left as free parameters. We then adjusted these free category variances to reproduce the empirical boundary between the two categories c 1 and c 2 for that language, as follows. Sweeping from left ( c 1 ) to right ( c 2 ), we took the model’s boundary between c 1 and c 2 to be the first position i on the spectrum for which p ( c 1 | i ) ≤ p ( c 2 | i ); we refer to this as the model crossover point . We measured the distance in the CIELAB-based spectrum between the model crossover point and the empirical category boundary, and adjusted the category variances σ c 1 2 and σ c 2 2 so as to minimize that distance. This was done separately for each language’s model. Fig 6 shows the resulting fits of category components to naming data for each of the three languages.

We then simulated performance in the 2AFC discrimination task for each stimulus pair in Table 5 , by each model, as follows. Given a pair of stimuli, one stimulus was taken to be the target t and therefore held in memory, and the other taken to be the distractor d . We took the reconstruction r for the target stimulus t to be the expected value of the posterior for the 2-category model:

We then measured, along the hue spectrum in question, the distance dist ( r , t ) between the reconstruction r and the target t , and the distance dist ( r , d ) between the reconstruction r and the distractor d . We converted each of these two distances to a similarity score:

and modeled the proportion correct choice as:

These equations are based on Luce’s [ 43 ] (pp. 113-114) model of choice behavior. For each pair of stimuli, each stimulus was once taken to be the target, and once taken to be the distractor, and the results averaged to yield a mean discrimination score for that pair. Scores were then averaged across all pairs listed as within-category pairs, and separately for all pairs listed as cross-category pairs. These scores were range-matched to the empirical data, in an attempt to correct for other factors that could affect performance, such as familiarity with such tasks, etc.; such external factors could in principle differ substantially across participant pools for the three languages modeled. We measured MSE between the model output and the data so treated, and adjusted the remaining parameter σ m 2 , corresponding to memory uncertainty, so as to minimize this MSE. This entire process was conducted two times. The first time, each language’s model was fit to that same language’s discrimination data. Then, to test whether native-language categories allow a better fit than the categories of another language, we fit the Berinmo model to the English discrimination data (and vice versa), and the Himba model to the English discrimination data (and vice versa).

The empirical data considered for this study are those of Figs 2 (English green/blue , 10 second delay), 3 (Berinmo wor/nol ), and 4 (Himba dumbu/borou ) of Hanley and Roberson (2011) [ 36 ]. These data were originally published by Roberson and Davidoff (2000) [ 8 ], Roberson et al. (2000) [ 9 ], and Roberson et al. (2005) [ 10 ], respectively. The Berinmo and Himba stimuli and data were the same as in our Study 2, but the English stimuli and data reanalyzed by Hanley and Roberson (2011) [ 36 ] Fig 2 were instead drawn from Table 1 of Roberson and Davidoff (2000) [ 8 ], reproduced here in Table 6 , and used for the English condition of this study. These stimuli for English were at lightness (value) level 4, rather than 5 as for the other two languages. We chose to ignore this difference for modeling purposes.

Any stimulus pair that includes a boundary color is considered to be a cross-category pair. All hues are at value (lightness) level 4, and chroma (saturation) level 8. 1s denotes a 1-step pair; 2s denotes a 2-step pair.

English - stimuli (boundary color = 7.5BG)
withinacross
5B-2.5B (1s)10BG-7.5BG (1s)
5B-10BG (2s)2.5B-7.5BG (2s)
2.5BG-10G (1s)7.5BG-5BG (1s)
5BG-10G (2s)10BG-5BG (2s)

All modeling procedures were identical to those of Study 2, with the exception that GE (target = good exemplar) and PE (target = poor exemplar) cases were disaggregated, and analyzed separately.

Acknowledgments

We thank Roland Baddeley, Paul Kay, Charles Kemp, Steven Piantadosi, and an anonymous reviewer for their comments.

Funding Statement

This research was supported by the National Science Foundation ( www.nsf.gov ) under grants DGE-1106400 (EC) and SBE-1041707 (YX, TR). Publication was made possible in part by support from the Berkeley Research Impact Initiative (BRII) sponsored by the UC Berkeley Library. The funders had no role in study design, data collection and analysis, decision to publish, or preparation of the manuscript.

Data Availability

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Back to Entry
  • Entry Contents
  • Entry Bibliography
  • Academic Tools
  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Supplement to Philosophy of Linguistics

Whorfianism.

Emergentists tend to follow Edward Sapir in taking an interest in interlinguistic and intralinguistic variation. Linguistic anthropologists have explicitly taken up the task of defending a famous claim associated with Sapir that connects linguistic variation to differences in thinking and cognition more generally. The claim is very often referred to as the Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis (though this is a largely infelicitous label, as we shall see).

This topic is closely related to various forms of relativism—epistemological, ontological, conceptual, and moral—and its general outlines are discussed elsewhere in this encyclopedia; see the section on language in the Summer 2015 archived version of the entry on relativism (§3.1). Cultural versions of moral relativism suggest that, given how much cultures differ, what is moral for you might depend on the culture you were brought up in. A somewhat analogous view would suggest that, given how much language structures differ, what is thinkable for you might depend on the language you use. (This is actually a kind of conceptual relativism, but it is generally called linguistic relativism, and we will continue that practice.)

Even a brief skim of the vast literature on the topic is not remotely plausible in this article; and the primary literature is in any case more often polemical than enlightening. It certainly holds no general answer to what science has discovered about the influences of language on thought. Here we offer just a limited discussion of the alleged hypothesis and the rhetoric used in discussing it, the vapid and not so vapid forms it takes, and the prospects for actually devising testable scientific hypotheses about the influence of language on thought.

Whorf himself did not offer a hypothesis. He presented his “new principle of linguistic relativity” (Whorf 1956: 214) as a fact discovered by linguistic analysis:

When linguists became able to examine critically and scientifically a large number of languages of widely different patterns, their base of reference was expanded; they experienced an interruption of phenomena hitherto held universal, and a whole new order of significances came into their ken. It was found that the background linguistic system (in other words, the grammar) of each language is not merely a reproducing instrument for voicing ideas but rather is itself the shaper of ideas, the program and guide for the individual’s mental activity, for his analysis of impressions, for his synthesis of his mental stock in trade. Formulation of ideas is not an independent process, strictly rational in the old sense, but is part of a particular grammar, and differs, from slightly to greatly, between different grammars. We dissect nature along lines laid down by our native languages. The categories and types that we isolate from the world of phenomena we do not find there because they stare every observer in the face; on the contrary, the world is presented in a kaleidoscopic flux of impressions which has to be organized by our minds—and this means largely by the linguistic systems in our minds. We cut nature up, organize it into concepts, and ascribe significances as we do, largely because we are parties to an agreement to organize it in this way—an agreement that holds throughout our speech community and is codified in the patterns of our language. The agreement is, of course, an implicit and unstated one, but its terms are absolutely obligatory ; we cannot talk at all except by subscribing to the organization and classification of data which the agreement decrees. (Whorf 1956: 212–214; emphasis in original)

Later, Whorf’s speculations about the “sensuously and operationally different” character of different snow types for “an Eskimo” (Whorf 1956: 216) developed into a familiar journalistic meme about the Inuit having dozens or scores or hundreds of words for snow; but few who repeat that urban legend recall Whorf’s emphasis on its being grammar, rather than lexicon, that cuts up and organizes nature for us.

In an article written in 1937, posthumously published in an academic journal (Whorf 1956: 87–101), Whorf clarifies what is most important about the effects of language on thought and world-view. He distinguishes ‘phenotypes’, which are overt grammatical categories typically indicated by morphemic markers, from what he called ‘cryptotypes’, which are covert grammatical categories, marked only implicitly by distributional patterns in a language that are not immediately apparent. In English, the past tense would be an example of a phenotype (it is marked by the - ed suffix in all regular verbs). Gender in personal names and common nouns would be an example of a cryptotype, not systematically marked by anything. In a cryptotype, “class membership of the word is not apparent until there is a question of using it or referring to it in one of these special types of sentence, and then we find that this word belongs to a class requiring some sort of distinctive treatment, which may even be the negative treatment of excluding that type of sentence” (p. 89).

Whorf’s point is the familiar one that linguistic structure is comprised, in part, of distributional patterns in language use that are not explicitly marked. What follows from this, according to Whorf, is not that the existing lexemes in a language (like its words for snow) comprise covert linguistic structure, but that patterns shared by word classes constitute linguistic structure. In ‘Language, mind, and reality’ (1942; published posthumously in Theosophist , a magazine published in India for the followers of the 19th-century spiritualist Helena Blavatsky) he wrote:

Because of the systematic, configurative nature of higher mind, the “patternment” aspect of language always overrides and controls the “lexation”…or name-giving aspect. Hence the meanings of specific words are less important than we fondly fancy. Sentences, not words, are the essence of speech, just as equations and functions, and not bare numbers, are the real meat of mathematics. We are all mistaken in our common belief that any word has an “exact meaning.” We have seen that the higher mind deals in symbols that have no fixed reference to anything, but are like blank checks, to be filled in as required, that stand for “any value” of a given variable, like …the x , y , z of algebra. (Whorf 1942: 258)

Whorf apparently thought that only personal and proper names have an exact meaning or reference (Whorf 1956: 259).

For Whorf, it was an unquestionable fact that language influences thought to some degree:

Actually, thinking is most mysterious, and by far the greatest light upon it that we have is thrown by the study of language. This study shows that the forms of a person’s thoughts are controlled by inexorable laws of pattern of which he is unconscious. These patterns are the unperceived intricate systematizations of his own language—shown readily enough by a candid comparison and contrast with other languages, especially those of a different linguistic family. His thinking itself is in a language—in English, in Sanskrit, in Chinese. [footnote omitted] And every language is a vast pattern-system, different from others, in which are culturally ordained the forms and categories by which the personality not only communicates, but analyzes nature, notices or neglects types of relationship and phenomena, channels his reasoning, and builds the house of his consciousness. (Whorf 1956: 252)

He seems to regard it as necessarily true that language affects thought, given

  • the fact that language must be used in order to think, and
  • the facts about language structure that linguistic analysis discovers.

He also seems to presume that the only structure and logic that thought has is grammatical structure. These views are not the ones that after Whorf’s death came to be known as ‘the Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis’ (a sobriquet due to Hoijer 1954). Nor are they what was called the ‘Whorf thesis’ by Brown and Lenneberg (1954) which was concerned with the relation of obligatory lexical distinctions and thought. Brown and Lenneberg (1954) investigated this question by looking at the relation of color terminology in a language and the classificatory abilities of the speakers of that language. The issue of the relation between obligatory lexical distinctions and thought is at the heart of what is now called ‘the Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis’ or ‘the Whorf Hypothesis’ or ‘Whorfianism’.

1. Banal Whorfianism

No one is going to be impressed with a claim that some aspect of your language may affect how you think in some way or other; that is neither a philosophical thesis nor a psychological hypothesis. So it is appropriate to set aside entirely the kind of so-called hypotheses that Steven Pinker presents in The Stuff of Thought (2007: 126–128) as “five banal versions of the Whorfian hypothesis”:

  • “Language affects thought because we get much of our knowledge through reading and conversation.”
  • “A sentence can frame an event, affecting the way people construe it.”
  • “The stock of words in a language reflects the kinds of things its speakers deal with in their lives and hence think about.”
  • “[I]f one uses the word language in a loose way to refer to meanings,… then language is thought.”
  • “When people think about an entity, among the many attributes they can think about is its name.”

These are just truisms, unrelated to any serious issue about linguistic relativism.

We should also set aside some methodological versions of linguistic relativism discussed in anthropology. It may be excellent advice to a budding anthropologist to be aware of linguistic diversity, and to be on the lookout for ways in which your language may affect your judgment of other cultures; but such advice does not constitute a hypothesis.

2. The so-called Sapir-Whorf hypothesis

The term “Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis” was coined by Harry Hoijer in his contribution (Hoijer 1954) to a conference on the work of Benjamin Lee Whorf in 1953. But anyone looking in Hoijer’s paper for a clear statement of the hypothesis will look in vain. Curiously, despite his stated intent “to review and clarify the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis” (1954: 93), Hoijer did not even attempt to state it. The closest he came was this:

The central idea of the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis is that language functions, not simply as a device for reporting experience, but also, and more significantly, as a way of defining experience for its speakers.

The claim that “language functions…as a way of defining experience” appears to be offered as a kind of vague metaphysical insight rather than either a statement of linguistic relativism or a testable hypothesis.

And if Hoijer seriously meant that what qualitative experiences a speaker can have are constituted by that speaker’s language, then surely the claim is false. There is no reason to doubt that non-linguistic sentient creatures like cats can experience (for example) pain or heat or hunger, so having a language is not a necessary condition for having experiences. And it is surely not sufficient either: a robot with a sophisticated natural language processing capacity could be designed without the capacity for conscious experience.

In short, it is a mystery what Hoijer meant by his “central idea”.

Vague remarks of the same loosely metaphysical sort have continued to be a feature of the literature down to the present. The statements made in some recent papers, even in respected refereed journals, contain non-sequiturs echoing some of the remarks of Sapir, Whorf, and Hoijer. And they come from both sides of the debate.

3. Anti-Whorfian rhetoric

Lila Gleitman is an Essentialist on the other side of the contemporary debate: she is against linguistic relativism, and against the broadly Whorfian work of Stephen Levinson’s group at the Max Planck Institute for Psycholinguistics. In the context of criticizing a particular research design, Li and Gleitman (2002) quote Whorf’s claim that “language is the factor that limits free plasticity and rigidifies channels of development”. But in the claim cited, Whorf seems to be talking about the psychological topic that holds universally of human conceptual development, not claiming that linguistic relativism is true.

Li and Gleitman then claim (p. 266) that such (Whorfian) views “have diminished considerably in academic favor” in part because of “the universalist position of Chomskian linguistics, with its potential for explaining the striking similarity of language learning in children all over the world.” But there is no clear conflict or even a conceptual connection between Whorf’s views about language placing limits on developmental plasticity, and Chomsky’s thesis of an innate universal architecture for syntax. In short, there is no reason why Chomsky’s I-languages could not be innately constrained, but (once acquired) cognitively and developmentally constraining.

For example, the supposedly deep linguistic universal of ‘recursion’ (Hauser et al. 2002) is surely quite independent of whether the inventory of colour-name lexemes in your language influences the speed with which you can discriminate between color chips. And conversely, universal tendencies in color naming across languages (Kay and Regier 2006) do not show that color-naming differences among languages are without effect on categorical perception (Thierry et al. 2009).

4. Strong and weak Whorfianism

One of the first linguists to defend a general form of universalism against linguistic relativism, thus presupposing that they conflict, was Julia Penn (1972). She was also an early popularizer of the distinction between ‘strong’ and ‘weak’ formulations of the Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis (and an opponent of the ‘strong’ version).

‘Weak’ versions of Whorfianism state that language influences or defeasibly shapes thought. ‘Strong’ versions state that language determines thought, or fixes it in some way. The weak versions are commonly dismissed as banal (because of course there must be some influence), and the stronger versions as implausible.

The weak versions are considered banal because they are not adequately formulated as testable hypotheses that could conflict with relevant evidence about language and thought.

Why would the strong versions be thought implausible? For a language to make us think in a particular way, it might seem that it must at least temporarily prevent us from thinking in other ways, and thus make some thoughts not only inexpressible but unthinkable. If this were true, then strong Whorfianism would conflict with the Katzian effability claim. There would be thoughts that a person couldn’t think because of the language(s) they speak.

Some are fascinated by the idea that there are inaccessible thoughts; and the notion that learning a new language gives access to entirely new thoughts and concepts seems to be a staple of popular writing about the virtues of learning languages. But many scientists and philosophers intuitively rebel against violations of effability: thinking about concepts that no one has yet named is part of their job description.

The resolution lies in seeing that the language could affect certain aspects of our cognitive functioning without making certain thoughts unthinkable for us .

For example, Greek has separate terms for what we call light blue and dark blue, and no word meaning what ‘blue’ means in English: Greek forces a choice on this distinction. Experiments have shown (Thierry et al. 2009) that native speakers of Greek react faster when categorizing light blue and dark blue color chips—apparently a genuine effect of language on thought. But that does not make English speakers blind to the distinction, or imply that Greek speakers cannot grasp the idea of a hue falling somewhere between green and violet in the spectrum.

There is no general or global ineffability problem. There is, though, a peculiar aspect of strong Whorfian claims, giving them a local analog of ineffability: the content of such a claim cannot be expressed in any language it is true of . This does not make the claims self-undermining (as with the standard objections to relativism); it doesn’t even mean that they are untestable. They are somewhat anomalous, but nothing follows concerning the speakers of the language in question (except that they cannot state the hypothesis using the basic vocabulary and grammar that they ordinarily use).

If there were a true hypothesis about the limits that basic English vocabulary and constructions puts on what English speakers can think, the hypothesis would turn out to be inexpressible in English, using basic vocabulary and the usual repertoire of constructions. That might mean it would be hard for us to discuss it in an article in English unless we used terminological innovations or syntactic workarounds. But that doesn’t imply anything about English speakers’ ability to grasp concepts, or to develop new ways of expressing them by coining new words or elaborated syntax.

5. Constructing and evaluating Whorfian hypotheses

A number of considerations are relevant to formulating, testing, and evaluating Whorfian hypotheses.

Genuine hypotheses about the effects of language on thought will always have a duality: there will be a linguistic part and a non-linguistic one. The linguistic part will involve a claim that some feature is present in one language but absent in another.

Whorf himself saw that it was only obligatory features of languages that established “mental patterns” or “habitual thought” (Whorf 1956: 139), since if it were optional then the speaker could optionally do it one way or do it the other way. And so this would not be a case of “constraining the conceptual structure”. So we will likewise restrict our attention to obligatory features here.

Examples of relevant obligatory features would include lexical distinctions like the light vs. dark blue forced choice in Greek, or the forced choice between “in (fitting tightly)” vs. “in (fitting loosely)” in Korean. They also include grammatical distinctions like the forced choice in Spanish 2nd-person pronouns between informal/intimate and formal/distant (informal tú vs. formal usted in the singular; informal vosotros vs. formal ustedes in the plural), or the forced choice in Tamil 1st-person plural pronouns between inclusive (“we = me and you and perhaps others”) and exclusive (“we = me and others not including you”).

The non-linguistic part of a Whorfian hypothesis will contrast the psychological effects that habitually using the two languages has on their speakers. For example, one might conjecture that the habitual use of Spanish induces its speakers to be sensitive to the formal and informal character of the speaker’s relationship with their interlocutor while habitually using English does not.

So testing Whorfian hypotheses requires testing two independent hypotheses with the appropriate kinds of data. In consequence, evaluating them requires the expertise of both linguistics and psychology, and is a multidisciplinary enterprise. Clearly, the linguistic hypothesis may hold up where the psychological hypothesis does not, or conversely.

In addition, if linguists discovered that some linguistic feature was optional in two different languages, then even if psychological experiments showed differences between the two populations of speakers, this would not show linguistic determination or influence. The cognitive differences might depend on (say) cultural differences.

A further important consideration concerns the strength of the inducement relationship that a Whorfian hypothesis posits between a speaker’s language and their non-linguistic capacities. The claim that your language shapes or influences your cognition is quite different from the claim that your language makes certain kinds of cognition impossible (or obligatory) for you. The strength of any Whorfian hypothesis will vary depending on the kind of relationship being claimed, and the ease of revisability of that relation.

A testable Whorfian hypothesis will have a schematic form something like this:

  • Linguistic part : Feature F is obligatory in L 1 but optional in L 2 .
  • Psychological part : Speaking a language with obligatory feature F bears relation R to the cognitive effect C .

The relation R might in principle be causation or determination, but it is important to see that it might merely be correlation, or slight favoring; and the non-linguistic cognitive effect C might be readily suppressible or revisable.

Dan Slobin (1996) presents a view that competes with Whorfian hypotheses as standardly understood. He hypothesizes that when the speakers are using their cognitive abilities in the service of a linguistic ability (speaking, writing, translating, etc.), the language they are planning to use to express their thought will have a temporary online effect on how they express their thought. The claim is that as long as language users are thinking in order to frame their speech or writing or translation in some language, the mandatory features of that language will influence the way they think.

On Slobin’s view, these effects quickly attenuate as soon as the activity of thinking for speaking ends. For example, if a speaker is thinking for writing in Spanish, then Slobin’s hypothesis would predict that given the obligatory formal/informal 2nd-person pronoun distinction they would pay greater attention to the formal/informal character of their social relationships with their audience than if they were writing in English. But this effect is not permanent. As soon as they stop thinking for speaking, the effect of Spanish on their thought ends.

Slobin’s non-Whorfian linguistic relativist hypothesis raises the importance of psychological research on bilinguals or people who currently use two or more languages with a native or near-native facility. This is because one clear way to test Slobin-like hypotheses relative to Whorfian hypotheses would be to find out whether language correlated non-linguistic cognitive differences between speakers hold for bilinguals only when are thinking for speaking in one language, but not when they are thinking for speaking in some other language. If the relevant cognitive differences appeared and disappeared depending on which language speakers were planning to express themselves in, it would go some way to vindicate Slobin-like hypotheses over more traditional Whorfian Hypotheses. Of course, one could alternately accept a broadening of Whorfian hypotheses to include Slobin-like evanescent effects. Either way, attention must be paid to the persistence and revisability of the linguistic effects.

Kousta et al. (2008) shows that “for bilinguals there is intraspeaker relativity in semantic representations and, therefore, [grammatical] gender does not have a conceptual, non-linguistic effect” (843). Grammatical gender is obligatory in the languages in which it occurs and has been claimed by Whorfians to have persistent and enduring non-linguistic effects on representations of objects (Boroditsky et al. 2003). However, Kousta et al. supports the claim that bilinguals’ semantic representations vary depending on which language they are using, and thus have transient effects. This suggests that although some semantic representations of objects may vary from language to language, their non-linguistic cognitive effects are transitory.

Some advocates of Whorfianism have held that if Whorfian hypotheses were true, then meaning would be globally and radically indeterminate. Thus, the truth of Whorfian hypotheses is equated with global linguistic relativism—a well known self-undermining form of relativism. But as we have seen, not all Whorfian hypotheses are global hypotheses: they are about what is induced by particular linguistic features. And the associated non-linguistic perceptual and cognitive differences can be quite small, perhaps insignificant. For example, Thierry et al. (2009) provides evidence that an obligatory lexical distinction between light and dark blue affects Greek speakers’ color perception in the left hemisphere only. And the question of the degree to which this affects sensuous experience is not addressed.

The fact that Whorfian hypotheses need not be global linguistic relativist hypotheses means that they do not conflict with the claim that there are language universals. Structuralists of the first half of the 20th century tended to disfavor the idea of universals: Martin Joos’s characterization of structuralist linguistics as claiming that “languages can differ without limit as to either extent or direction” (Joos 1966, 228) has been much quoted in this connection. If the claim that languages can vary without limit were conjoined with the claim that languages have significant and permanent effects on the concepts and worldview of their speakers, a truly profound global linguistic relativism would result. But neither conjunct should be accepted. Joos’s remark is regarded by nearly all linguists today as overstated (and merely a caricature of the structuralists), and Whorfian hypotheses do not have to take a global or deterministic form.

John Lucy, a conscientious and conservative researcher of Whorfian hypotheses, has remarked:

We still know little about the connections between particular language patterns and mental life—let alone how they operate or how significant they are…a mere handful of empirical studies address the linguistic relativity proposal directly and nearly all are conceptually flawed. (Lucy 1996, 37)

Although further empirical studies on Whorfian hypotheses have been completed since Lucy published his 1996 review article, it is hard to find any that have satisfied the criteria of:

  • adequately utilizing both the relevant linguistic and psychological research,
  • focusing on obligatory rather than optional linguistic features,
  • stating hypotheses in a clear testable way, and
  • ruling out relevant competing Slobin-like hypotheses.

There is much important work yet to be done on testing the range of Whorfian hypotheses and other forms of linguistic conceptual relativism, and on understanding the significance of any Whorfian hypotheses that turn out to be well supported.

Copyright © 2024 by Barbara C. Scholz Francis Jeffry Pelletier < francisp @ ualberta . ca > Geoffrey K. Pullum < pullum @ gmail . com > Ryan Nefdt < ryan . nefdt @ uct . ac . za >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2024 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Encyclopedia Britannica

  • History & Society
  • Science & Tech
  • Biographies
  • Animals & Nature
  • Geography & Travel
  • Arts & Culture
  • Games & Quizzes
  • On This Day
  • One Good Fact
  • New Articles
  • Lifestyles & Social Issues
  • Philosophy & Religion
  • Politics, Law & Government
  • World History
  • Health & Medicine
  • Browse Biographies
  • Birds, Reptiles & Other Vertebrates
  • Bugs, Mollusks & Other Invertebrates
  • Environment
  • Fossils & Geologic Time
  • Entertainment & Pop Culture
  • Sports & Recreation
  • Visual Arts
  • Demystified
  • Image Galleries
  • Infographics
  • Top Questions
  • Britannica Kids
  • Saving Earth
  • Space Next 50
  • Student Center
  • Introduction

Critiques and evidence

Benjamin Lee Whorf

  • When did science begin?
  • Where was science invented?

Blackboard inscribed with scientific formulas and calculations in physics and mathematics

Whorfian hypothesis

Our editors will review what you’ve submitted and determine whether to revise the article.

  • Table Of Contents

Benjamin Lee Whorf

Whorfian hypothesis , in linguistics , a hypothesis given classic form by the American linguist Benjamin Lee Whorf stating that language influences thought and perception of reality. It is also called linguistic relativity, because it focuses on how different languages lead to differences in perception. Although Whorf did not distinguish between different iterations of his hypothesis, scholars have since discussed “strong” and “weak” versions based on how strong an impact of language on perception is supposed. The strong Whorfian hypothesis suggests that language determines a speaker’s perception of the world. Weak versions of the hypothesis simply state that language influences perception to some degree. The weak hypothesis allows for translation and shared understanding between disparate languages, while the strong hypothesis suggests that translation and shared understanding may be impossible in certain circumstances. With the development and popularization of Chomskyan linguistics and its focus on universal grammar , the Whorfian hypothesis has largely fallen out of favor.

In the 18th and 19th centuries the German scholars Johann Gottfried von Herder and Wilhelm von Humboldt first suggested that the structure of a language conditions speakers’ perception of the world. Later the American anthropologist Franz Boas and his student Edward Sapir , who studied linguistics as a subdiscipline of anthropology , found Humboldt’s idea of the connection between language and culture compelling. In the 1920s and ’30s Sapir suggested that humans perceive the world principally through language, and he wrote many articles on the relationship of language to culture. A thorough description of a linguistic structure and its function in speech might, he wrote in 1931, provide insight into humans’ perceptive and cognitive faculties and help explain the diverse behavior among peoples of different cultural backgrounds.

sapir whorf hypothesis evidence

It was left to one of Sapir’s students, Whorf, to present the hypothesis in a sufficiently challenging form to attract widespread scholarly attention. Whorf developed the concept of the equation of culture and language based on his study of the Hopi and Shawnee languages, spoken originally in the Southwest and in the central Ohio River valley of what is now the United States , respectively. He concluded that what speakers of these languages perceived was itself different from what English-speaking Americans perceived, by virtue of the way their languages were structured. He suggested, for example, that the way a people views time and punctuality is influenced by the types of verbal tenses in their language. Namely, he argued that the verb tenses of English lead to a three-part division of time (past, present, future) while Hopi’s verb tenses lead to a two-part division (manifested [past and present] and manifesting [future]). Hence, the structures of different languages lead the speakers of those languages to view the world in different ways. Whorf further concluded that the formulation of ideas is part of (or influenced by) a particular grammar and differs as grammars differ. Since the republication of Whorf’s more important papers in 1956, the thesis that language determines perception and thought has come to be known as the Whorfian (or Sapir-Whorf) hypothesis, or the theory of linguistic relativity. See also ethnolinguistics .

sapir whorf hypothesis evidence

The Whorfian hypothesis has faced criticism since at least the 1970s. Strong versions of the hypothesis (that language determines perception) are largely rejected by modern linguists. Such iterations of the hypothesis suggest that translation may be impossible in certain cases. Most scholars now agree that translation is generally possible, even if a pithy utterance in one language must be changed into a convoluted one in another. A strong application of the hypothesis also implies that there are some thoughts that are impossible for people to have on the basis of their language, which many scholars similarly find unlikely. Weaker versions of the Whorfian hypothesis (that language merely influences perception) have been criticized for not being formulated as falsifiable hypotheses .

Some empirical studies have attempted, with mixed results, to test the Whorfian hypothesis, using measures such as the perception of color . For example, in a 2009 study , cognitive neuroscientist Guillaume Thierry and colleagues concluded that Greek speakers can tell light blue from dark blue more readily than their English -speaking counterparts, because Greek has separate words for the two colors. Psycholinguists Mark Lowry and Judith Bryant (2019) argued that the impact of language on color perception is minimal but that language does have an impact on color memory. However, cognitive psychologist Oliver Wright and colleagues found, as stated by the title of a 2015 paper they authored, that “Whorfian effects on colour memory are not reliable.”

  • Subject List
  • Take a Tour
  • For Authors
  • Subscriber Services
  • Publications
  • African American Studies
  • African Studies
  • American Literature

Anthropology

  • Architecture Planning and Preservation
  • Art History
  • Atlantic History
  • Biblical Studies
  • British and Irish Literature
  • Childhood Studies
  • Chinese Studies
  • Cinema and Media Studies
  • Communication
  • Criminology
  • Environmental Science
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • International Law
  • International Relations
  • Islamic Studies
  • Jewish Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Latino Studies
  • Linguistics
  • Literary and Critical Theory
  • Medieval Studies
  • Military History
  • Political Science
  • Public Health
  • Renaissance and Reformation
  • Social Work
  • Urban Studies
  • Victorian Literature
  • Browse All Subjects

How to Subscribe

  • Free Trials

In This Article Expand or collapse the "in this article" section Whorfian Hypothesis

Introduction, general overviews and foundational texts.

  • Anti-Whorfian Literature
  • Pro-Whorfian Literature
  • Counterfactual Reasoning
  • Theory of Mind

Related Articles Expand or collapse the "related articles" section about

About related articles close popup.

Lorem Ipsum Sit Dolor Amet

Vestibulum ante ipsum primis in faucibus orci luctus et ultrices posuere cubilia Curae; Aliquam ligula odio, euismod ut aliquam et, vestibulum nec risus. Nulla viverra, arcu et iaculis consequat, justo diam ornare tellus, semper ultrices tellus nunc eu tellus.

  • Cognitive Anthropology
  • Edward Sapir
  • Ethnocentrism
  • Ethnoscience
  • Language and Urban Place
  • Linguistic Anthropology
  • Linguistic Relativity

Other Subject Areas

Forthcoming articles expand or collapse the "forthcoming articles" section.

  • Landscape Archaeology
  • Medical Activism
  • Transhumance
  • Find more forthcoming articles...
  • Export Citations
  • Share This Facebook LinkedIn Twitter

Whorfian Hypothesis by Daniel Casasanto LAST REVIEWED: 11 January 2012 LAST MODIFIED: 11 January 2012 DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780199766567-0058

The Sapir-Whorf hypothesis (a.k.a. the Whorfian hypothesis) concerns the relationship between language and thought. Neither the anthropological linguist Edward Sapir (b. 1884–d. 1939) nor his student Benjamin Whorf (b. 1897–d. 1941) ever formally stated any single hypothesis about the influence of language on nonlinguistic cognition and perception. On the basis of their writings, however, two proposals emerged, generating decades of controversy among anthropologists, linguists, philosophers, and psychologists. According to the more radical proposal, linguistic determinism , the languages that people speak rigidly determine the way they perceive and understand the world. On the more moderate proposal, linguistic relativity , habits of using language influence habits of thinking. As a result, people who speak different languages think differently in predictable ways. During the latter half of the 20th century, the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis was widely regarded as false. Around the turn of the 21st century, however, experimental evidence reopened debate about the extent to which language shapes nonlinguistic cognition and perception. Scientific tests of linguistic determinism and linguistic relativity help to clarify what is universal in the human mind and what depends on the particulars of people’s physical and social experience.

Writing on the relationship between language and thought predates Sapir and Whorf, and extends beyond the academy. The 19th-century German philosopher Wilhelm von Humboldt argued that language constrains people’s worldview, foreshadowing the idea of linguistic determinism later articulated in Sapir 1929 and Whorf 1956 ( Humboldt 1988 ). The intuition that language radically determines thought has been explored in works of fiction such as Orwell’s dystopian fantasy 1984 ( Orwell 1949 ). Although there is little empirical support for radical linguistic determinism, more moderate forms of linguistic relativity continue to generate influential research, reviewed from an anthropologist’s perspective in Lucy 1997 , from a psychologist’s perspective in Hunt and Agnoli 1991 , and discussed from multidisciplinary perspectives in Gumperz and Levinson 1996 and Gentner and Goldin-Meadow 2003 .

Gentner, Dedre, and Susan Goldin-Meadow, eds. 2003. Language in mind: Advances in the study of language and thought . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Edited volume containing position papers for and against linguistic relativity. Includes reviews of some of the experimental studies that revived widespread interest in the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis at the beginning of the 21st century.

Gumperz, John J., and Stephen C. Levinson, eds. 1996. Rethinking linguistic relativity . Studies in the Social and Cultural Foundations of Language 17. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Univ. Press.

Edited volume containing position papers for and against linguistic relativity. A cross-section of Whorfian research in anthropology, psychology, and linguistics at the end of the 20th century.

Humboldt, Wilhelm von. 1988. On language: The diversity of human language-structure and its influence on the mental development of mankind . Translated by Peter Heath. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Univ. Press.

Humboldt argues that language determines one’s world view.

Hunt, Earl, and Franca Agnoli. 1991. The Whorfian hypothesis: A cognitive psychology perspective. Psychological Review 98.3: 377–389.

DOI: 10.1037/0033-295X.98.3.377

A critical review of 20th-century Whorfian research, in which the authors sketch proposals for several studies that were brought to fruition by other researchers over the ensuing two decades.

Lucy, John A. 1997. Linguistic relativity. Annual Review of Anthropology 26:291–312.

DOI: 10.1146/annurev.anthro.26.1.291

A review focusing on the various ways in which the Whorfian question was approached empirically during the 20th century.

Orwell, George. 1949. 1984: A novel . New York: Harcourt, Brace.

Fictitious account of a totalitarian state in which language is used to control thought.

Sapir, E. 1929. The status of linguistics as a science. Language 5:207–214.

DOI: 10.2307/409588

Sapir states the view that language shapes one’s worldview, subsequently called linguistic determinism.

Whorf, Benjamin Lee. 1956. Language, thought, and reality: Selected writings of Benjamin Lee Whorf . Edited by John B. Carroll. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

The definitive collection of Whorf’s writings, some posthumously published.

back to top

Users without a subscription are not able to see the full content on this page. Please subscribe or login .

Oxford Bibliographies Online is available by subscription and perpetual access to institutions. For more information or to contact an Oxford Sales Representative click here .

  • About Anthropology »
  • Meet the Editorial Board »
  • Africa, Anthropology of
  • Agriculture
  • Animal Cultures
  • Animal Ritual
  • Animal Sanctuaries
  • Anorexia Nervosa
  • Anthropocene, The
  • Anthropological Activism and Visual Ethnography
  • Anthropology and Education
  • Anthropology and Theology
  • Anthropology of Islam
  • Anthropology of Kurdistan
  • Anthropology of the Senses
  • Anthrozoology
  • Antiquity, Ethnography in
  • Applied Anthropology
  • Archaeobotany
  • Archaeological Education
  • Archaeologies of Sexuality
  • Archaeology
  • Archaeology and Museums
  • Archaeology and Political Evolution
  • Archaeology and Race
  • Archaeology and the Body
  • Archaeology, Gender and
  • Archaeology, Global
  • Archaeology, Historical
  • Archaeology, Indigenous
  • Archaeology of Childhood
  • Archaeology of the Senses
  • Art Museums
  • Art/Aesthetics
  • Autoethnography
  • Bakhtin, Mikhail
  • Bass, William M.
  • Benedict, Ruth
  • Binford, Lewis
  • Bioarchaeology
  • Biocultural Anthropology
  • Biological and Physical Anthropology
  • Biological Citizenship
  • Boas, Franz
  • Bone Histology
  • Bureaucracy
  • Business Anthropology
  • Cargo Cults
  • Charles Sanders Peirce and Anthropological Theory
  • Christianity, Anthropology of
  • Citizenship
  • Class, Archaeology and
  • Clinical Trials
  • Cobb, William Montague
  • Code-switching and Multilingualism
  • Cole, Johnnetta
  • Colonialism
  • Commodities
  • Consumerism
  • Crapanzano, Vincent
  • Cultural Heritage Presentation and Interpretation
  • Cultural Heritage, Race and
  • Cultural Materialism
  • Cultural Relativism
  • Cultural Resource Management
  • Culture and Personality
  • Culture, Popular
  • Curatorship
  • Cyber-Archaeology
  • Dalit Studies
  • Dance Ethnography
  • de Heusch, Luc
  • Deaccessioning
  • Design, Anthropology and
  • Digital Anthropology
  • Disability and Deaf Studies and Anthropology
  • Douglas, Mary
  • Drake, St. Clair
  • Durkheim and the Anthropology of Religion
  • Economic Anthropology
  • Embodied/Virtual Environments
  • Emotion, Anthropology of
  • Environmental Anthropology
  • Environmental Justice and Indigeneity
  • Ethnoarchaeology
  • Ethnographic Documentary Production
  • Ethnographic Films from Iran
  • Ethnography
  • Ethnography Apps and Games
  • Ethnohistory and Historical Ethnography
  • Ethnomusicology
  • Evans-Pritchard, E. E.
  • Evolution, Cultural
  • Evolutionary Cognitive Archaeology
  • Evolutionary Theory
  • Experimental Archaeology
  • Federal Indian Law
  • Feminist Anthropology
  • Film, Ethnographic
  • Forensic Anthropology
  • Francophonie
  • Frazer, Sir James George
  • Geertz, Clifford
  • Gender and Religion
  • GIS and Archaeology
  • Global Health
  • Globalization
  • Gluckman, Max
  • Graphic Anthropology
  • Haraway, Donna
  • Healing and Religion
  • Health and Social Stratification
  • Health Policy, Anthropology of
  • Heritage Language
  • House Museums
  • Human Adaptability
  • Human Evolution
  • Human Rights
  • Human Rights Films
  • Humanistic Anthropology
  • Hurston, Zora Neale
  • Identity Politics
  • India, Masculinity, Identity
  • Indigeneity
  • Indigenous Boarding School Experiences
  • Indigenous Economic Development
  • Indigenous Media: Currents of Engagement
  • Industrial Archaeology
  • Institutions
  • Interpretive Anthropology
  • Intertextuality and Interdiscursivity
  • Laboratories
  • Language and Emotion
  • Language and Law
  • Language and Media
  • Language and Race
  • Language Contact and its Sociocultural Contexts, Anthropol...
  • Language Ideology
  • Language Socialization
  • Leakey, Louis
  • Legal Anthropology
  • Legal Pluralism
  • Levantine Archaeology
  • Liberalism, Anthropology of
  • Linguistics, Historical
  • Literary Anthropology
  • Local Biologies
  • Lévi-Strauss, Claude
  • Malinowski, Bronisław
  • Margaret Mead, Gregory Bateson, and Visual Anthropology
  • Maritime Archaeology
  • Material Culture
  • Materiality
  • Mathematical Anthropology
  • Matriarchal Studies
  • Mead, Margaret
  • Media Anthropology
  • Medical Anthropology
  • Medical Technology and Technique
  • Mediterranean
  • Mendel, Gregor
  • Mental Health and Illness
  • Mesoamerican Archaeology
  • Mexican Migration to the United States
  • Militarism, Anthropology and
  • Missionization
  • Morgan, Lewis Henry
  • Multimodal Ethnography
  • Multispecies Ethnography
  • Museum Anthropology
  • Museum Education
  • Museum Studies
  • NAGPRA and Repatriation of Native American Human Remains a...
  • Narrative in Sociocultural Studies of Language
  • Nationalism
  • Needham, Rodney
  • Neoliberalism
  • NGOs, Anthropology of
  • Niche Construction
  • Northwest Coast, The
  • Oceania, Archaeology of
  • Paleolithic Art
  • Paleontology
  • Performance Studies
  • Performativity
  • Perspectivism
  • Philosophy of Museums
  • Plantations
  • Political Anthropology
  • Postprocessual Archaeology
  • Postsocialism
  • Poverty, Culture of
  • Primatology
  • Primitivism and Race in Ethnographic Film: A Decolonial Re...
  • Processual Archaeology
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Psychological Anthropology
  • Public Archaeology
  • Public Sociocultural Anthropologies
  • Religion and Post-Socialism
  • Religious Conversion
  • Repatriation
  • Reproductive and Maternal Health in Anthropology
  • Reproductive Technologies
  • Rhetoric Culture Theory
  • Rural Anthropology
  • Sahlins, Marshall
  • Sapir, Edward
  • Scandinavia
  • Science Studies
  • Secularization
  • Settler Colonialism
  • Sex Estimation
  • Sign Language
  • Skeletal Age Estimation
  • Social Anthropology (British Tradition)
  • Social Movements
  • Socialization
  • Society for Visual Anthropology, History of
  • Socio-Cultural Approaches to the Anthropology of Reproduct...
  • Sociolinguistics
  • Sound Ethnography
  • Space and Place
  • Stable Isotopes
  • Stan Brakhage and Ethnographic Praxis
  • Structuralism
  • Studying Up
  • Sub-Saharan Africa, Democracy in
  • Surrealism and Anthropology
  • Technological Organization
  • Trans Studies in Anthroplogy
  • Transnationalism
  • Tree-Ring Dating
  • Turner, Edith L. B.
  • Turner, Victor
  • University Museums
  • Urban Anthropology
  • Virtual Ethnography
  • Visual Anthropology
  • Whorfian Hypothesis
  • Willey, Gordon
  • Wolf, Eric R.
  • Writing Culture
  • Youth Culture
  • Zora Neale Hurston and Visual Anthropology
  • Privacy Policy
  • Cookie Policy
  • Legal Notice
  • Accessibility

Powered by:

  • [185.194.105.172]
  • 185.194.105.172

IMAGES

  1. Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis: Examples, Definition, Criticisms (2024)

    sapir whorf hypothesis evidence

  2. What is the Sapir Whorf Hypothesis?

    sapir whorf hypothesis evidence

  3. Sapir Whorf Hypothesis Explained

    sapir whorf hypothesis evidence

  4. PPT

    sapir whorf hypothesis evidence

  5. Sapir–Whorf hypothesis (Linguistic Relativity Hypothesis)

    sapir whorf hypothesis evidence

  6. SOLUTION: What is the sapir whorf hypothesis

    sapir whorf hypothesis evidence

VIDEO

  1. Sapir -whorf hypothesis .important topic meg-4 , part -1

  2. Sapir wharf hypothesis

  3. Saphir-whorf hypothesis

  4. What is the Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis? #facts #linguistics #shorts

  5. شرح علم اللغة جابتر 20 جزء 5 The Sapir–Whorf Hypothesis and Against the Sapir–Whorf Hypothesis

  6. History of Parapsychology