• 0 Shopping Cart $ 0.00 -->

Dodd School of Real Estate

Article 16 Case Study

Review the case study based on Article 16 that you€™ll find on the following pages, then, answer the questions. The case study is based on the Case Interpretations found in the NAR Code of Ethics and Arbitration Manual. Click here to open the document. Case Study REALTOR速 Barbara has an exclusive listing on Sue€™s property. […]

  • Google Plus

BerkshireRealtors

The voice of real estate.

  • Pittsfield Officially Declares April Fair Housing Month
  • REALTOR Community Service Spring Kickoff
  • Fair Housing Field Guide
  • Wow, that's a lot of towns
  • Dispelling 7 Myths About NAR's Proposed Settlement
  • Learning about schools made easy!
  • Take Action to Stop the Home Sales Tax
  • Meals for Good 2024
  • May Continuing Education
  • Fair Housing Month: Let's all remember....

in article 16 case study 1 sue refused

Code of Ethics Case Study – Article 16

Client A gave a 180-day exclusive right to sell listing of a commercial property to Realtor ® B, specifying that no “for sale” sign was to be placed on the property. Realtor ® B and his sales associates started an intensive sales effort which, after three months, had produced no offer to buy. But it had called attention to the fact that Client A’s property was for sale. When Realtor ® C heard of it, he called on Client A, saying that he understood that his property was, or soon would be, for sale, and that if Client A would list the property with him exclusively he felt confident that he could provide prompt action. Client A said the property was exclusively listed with Realtor ® B under a contract that still had about 90 days to run.

“In that case,” said Realtor ® C, “you are bound for the next 90 days to Realtor ® B. I have a really outstanding organization, constantly in touch with active buyers interested in this class of property. I am in a position to render you an exceptional service, and I will plan to call you again in 90 days or so.”

The property remained unsold during the term of Realtor ® B’s listing contract. Realtor ® C called again on Client A, and obtained his assurance that he would sign an exclusive listing of the property upon expiration of the listing contract.

When Realtor ® B called on Client A on the last day of the listing contract to seek its renewal, Client A told him of Realtor ® C’s two visits. “I was impressed by Realtor ® C’s assurance of superior service” Client A told Realtor ® B, “and in view of the fact that my listing with you produced no definite offer in the 180-day period, I have decided to give Realtor ® C a listing tomorrow.”

Realtor ® B filed a complaint with the Grievance Committee of the Board, outlined the facts, and charged that Realtor ® C’s conduct had been inconsistent with Article 16 of the Code of Ethics.

The Grievance Committee referred the matter to the Professional Standards Committee.

At the conclusion of the hearing, the panel found that Realtor ® C had violated Article 16 by failing to respect the exclusive agency of Realtor ® B . The panel’s decision advised that Realtor ® C’s original contact with Client A, made at a time when he had no knowledge of Realtor ® B’s exclusive listing, was not in itself unethical, but that as soon as he learned of Realtor ® B’s status as the client’s exclusive agent, he should have taken an attitude of respect for the agency of another Realtor ® , and refrained from any effort to get the listing until after the expiration date of the original contract.

Realtor ® C’s attitude of regarding the client’s relationship with Realtor ® B as a kind of misfortune, of presenting his own service as superior to Realtor ® B’s, and of suggesting to the client that, having a better capacity to serve him, he could wait until Realtor ® B’s listing had expired, was, the panel said, contrary to the respect for another Realtor ® ’s exclusive agency required by Article 16.

The Hearing Panel’s decision further advised Realtor ® C that he would have conducted himself in accord with Article 16 if, upon learning of Realtor ® B’s status as exclusive agent, he had expressed his willingness to cooperate with Realtor ® B in the sale of Client A’s property.

  • Click to share on Facebook (Opens in new window)
  • Click to share on Twitter (Opens in new window)
  • Click to share on Pinterest (Opens in new window)
  • Click to share on LinkedIn (Opens in new window)
  • Click to print (Opens in new window)
  • Click to email a link to a friend (Opens in new window)

Privacy Overview

Switch to ADA Accessible Theme

  • Toll Free 800-566-4101
  • Kingston, NY 845-331-4100
  • Marlboro, NY 845-236-4411

Facebook

Negligence of Multiple Parties: Article 16 in a Personal Injury Case

Man calling help after car crash accident on the road

In the ideal case, personal injury liability is clear: A negligent driver fails to stop at a stop sign and careens into a pedestrian. That driver is liable for the injuries and other damages caused. In practice, however, it’s often less clear-cut. Perhaps the driver was distracted, but when they did try to slam the brakes, their brakes failed. It so happens that their brakes were defectively designed, being prone to failure under certain circumstances. Now, the distracted driver and the auto manufacturer are both partially to blame. Who does the pedestrian sue? Continue reading to learn about multiple-party liability and New York’s Article 16. If you were injured in a car or truck accident in the Hudson Valley, call an experienced Kingston traffic accident lawyer for help.

CPLR Article 16

Historically, when multiple parties (known as “tortfeasors”) were at fault for a plaintiff’s injuries, each and every tortfeasor could be sued for the full amount of the plaintiff’s damages. In the example given above, even if a jury would determine that the driver was 40% at fault for the accident and the manufacturer of the faulty brakes was 60% at fault, the driver could be held liable for the plaintiff’s full damages. In 1966, New York amended the state’s Civil Practice Law & Rules (CPLR) to add Article 16.

Under Article 16, defendants who are less than 50% at fault for a given accident can only be held liable for their percentage of fault. If our negligent driver was 40% at fault and the injured pedestrian’s damages total $100,000, the driver can only be held liable for $40,000. If the pedestrian wants to collect their full $100,000, they’ll need to sue the auto manufacturer as well and split their claims.

Notably, Article 16 applies only to non-economic damages, meaning things like pain and suffering and emotional distress. Medical bills, lost wages, and other economic damages are not limited by Article 16. Additionally, the plaintiff may be able to get around Article 16 with regard to a particular party if they prove that, despite their due diligence, they are unable to sue the other liable party.

How Does Article 16 Affect Your Case?

If you were injured in a car or truck accident in New York, it’s important to know who all may be held liable and to include all potential parties in your action. To maximize your non-economic damages (pain and suffering, etc .), you’ll need to attach all relevant parties to the case. If you only sue one party, and the judge or jury determines that the party is less than 50% responsible for your accident, then you will be limited to their proportion of fault in your non-economic claims.

For your economic claims, however, you can pursue full damages against any liable party. The defendant can then turn around and pursue other liable parties to recover the appropriate portion of the damages they paid. In the example given above, if you sued the driver for 100% of your economic damages (let’s say $30,000), then you can collect $30,000 from the driver. The driver would then need to pursue the auto manufacturer, prove the auto manufacturer was 60% liable, and file a claim to recover $18,000 (or 60% of your claim against the driver).

Trusted Advice and Effective Representation for Your Hudson Valley Car Accident Claim

If you or someone you love has been hurt by a negligent driver in New York, find out if you’re entitled to money damages for your injuries by contacting the passionate and trial-ready Hudson Valley car crash lawyers at Rusk, Wadlin, Heppner & Martuscello, LLP for a free consultation at 845-331-4100 (Kingston) or 845-236-4411 (Marlboro).

Facebook

  • Brain Injury
  • Vehicle Accidents
  • Construction Accidents
  • Slip & Fall
  • Trusts & Estates
  • Medicaid Planning & Applications
  • Real Estate

Free Consultation - Available 24/7

  • About Our NYC Personal Injury Law Firm
  • Our Attorneys
  • Car Accidents
  • Construction Accidents
  • Motorcycle Accidents
  • Pedestrian Accidents
  • Slip & Fall
  • Case Results
  • Contact our New York City Law Office

What Is Article 16 in a Personal Injury Case?

Rosenbaum & Rosenbaum, P.C. | August 8, 2020 | Personal Injury

Most personal injury lawsuits typically involve two parties. The party who was injured is the plaintiff in the lawsuit, and the party who caused the injury is the defendant. The plaintiff seeks compensation for injuries and damages from the defendant. 

However, some personal injury cases involve multiple parties. Several parties might be responsible for causing the person’s injuries. For example, truck accident cases often involve multiple defendants, such as the truck driver and trucking company. 

A car accident claim could have multiple defendants if several cars were involved in the accident. Medical malpractice claims and product liability claims also tend to involve multiple defendants.

Article 16 applies in cases that involve multiple defendants. It determines how much money each party may have to pay if a jury determines they are responsible for causing the plaintiff’s injuries and damages.

What is Article 16?

Article 16 is a section of the New York Consolidated Laws Civil Practice Laws & Rules (CPLR). CPLR §1601 explains the law regarding the limited liability of persons who are jointly liable for damages in a personal injury case. 

Before Article 16 was enacted in 1966, any party responsible for causing an accident could be held liable for the entire amount of damages sustained because of the accident. In other words, if three parties were responsible for causing an injury, any one of those parties could be liable for the full amount of damages.

However, under Article 16, any party who has less than 50 percent fault for the cause of the accident can limit their damages. Their damages are limited to the percentage of fault. In other words, if a party is 30 percent at fault for the cause of an accident, that party only has to pay 30 percent of the damages.

If any party’s liability for the cause of the accident is 50 percent or higher, the plaintiff can seek full compensation for all damages from that party.

Article 16 does not apply in cases involving wrongful death. It also does not apply to property damage claims. 

Article 16 Only Applies to Noneconomic Damages

Article 16 applies to noneconomic damages in a personal injury case. Noneconomic damages refer to the “pain and suffering” a person sustains because of the accident or injury. 

Non-economic loss is defined in Article 16 as:

  • Pain and suffering
  • Mental anguish
  • Loss of consortium
  • Other damages for noneconomic loss

In most personal injury cases, noneconomic loss also includes damages such as scarring, disfigurement, loss of enjoyment of life, emotional distress, disability, and permanent impairment.

Article 16 Does Not Apply to Financial Damages

When there are multiple parties involved in a personal injury claim, all parties are jointly and severally liable for financial damages. Financial damages in an injury case include, but are not limited to:

  • Medical expenses
  • Loss of income
  • Personal care
  • Loss of earning potential
  • Travel expenses

A plaintiff can recover all financial losses from any defendant for a personal injury claim. For instance, if a dog owner and property owner share liability for a dog bite claim , the victim can recover financial losses from either defendant.

The defendants can pursue legal claims against each other for reimbursement of a portion of the damages according to their percentage of fault. 

What Happens When the Plaintiff is Partially at Fault?

In some personal injury cases, a plaintiff could have some liability for the cause of the accident. For example, a motorcyclist could have been speeding at the time of the motorcycle accident . A jury might find that the motorcyclist was partially to blame for the cause of the crash.

If so, another section of the CPLR governs how damages are divided among the parties.

Under CPLR §1411, the plaintiff’s damages can be reduced by the plaintiff’s percentage of fault for the cause of the accident. This theory is known as comparative fault .

For example, if the jury finds the motorcyclist is 20 percent at fault for the accident, the compensation paid to the rider is reduced by 20 percent.

New York adopted a pure comparative fault standard. Under this standard, there is no bar to the plaintiff’s percentage of fault. A person could be 99 percent responsible for the cause of his or her injury and still recover one percent of the damages from the defendants.

Dividing Fault in Personal Injury Cases

Insurance companies often try to use Article 16 or comparative fault to avoid liability or a claim. It is generally a wise decision to seek advice and guidance from an experienced personal injury lawyer whenever there are multiple parties involved in a case, or the at-fault party tries to blame the victim for causing the accident. 

Contact Our Personal Injury Law Firm in New York City

If you’ve been injured in an accident in Manhattan, NY , and need legal help, contact our New York City personal injury lawyers at Rosenbaum & Rosenbaum, P.C. to schedule a free consultation.

Rosenbaum & Rosenbaum, P.C. 100 Wall St 15th Floor New York, NY 10005 (212) 514-5007

Recent Posts

  • Can Trucks Drive in the Left Lane in New York?
  • Examples of Proximate Cause in a Personal Injury Case
  • What New York Cities Have the Most Car Accidents?
  • How Long Does It Take State Farm to Settle Claims in New York City?
  • What Does a Car Accident Lawyer Do in New York City? 
  • Clinical Ethics Services
  • Ethical AI Services
  • Custom Workshops
  • Medical Student Education
  • In the News
  • Impact Videos and Stories
  • Frequently Asked Questions
  • Policies, Disclosures and Reports

Practical Bioethics

The Case of Jehovah’s Witness: A Minor Requiring Blood Products

The case of jehovah's witness: a minor requiring blood products.

Case Study: Novak V. Cobb County – Kennestone Hospital – Blood Transfusions Auth. N.D. Ga. 1994, 849 F. Supp. 1559 Summary (Facts) A sixteen-year-old male member of Jehovah’s Witnesses incurred injuries in an auto accident. The injuries required surgery. He had informed both ambulance personnel and  the hospital of his wish not to receive blood transfusions. Surgery was performed without use of blood transfusions. Frequent blood tests revealed steadily declining hemoglobin and hematocrit readings. Physicians attempted to persuade patient and his mother (divorced, with custody of her son) to consent to blood transfusion, but they resolutely declined. After the surgeon expressed his opinion that patient was in imminent danger of life-threatening consequences, legal counsel for the hospital filed a late afternoon petition in the state court for appointment of a guardian ad litem, without notice to either the patient or his mother. On same evening, informal hearing was held by the state judge, attended by only the hospital’s risk manager and two hospital attorneys. The state judge appointed a guardian ad litem. The following morning, the state judge was told by the risk manager that the patient’s condition had deteriorated more during the night. The judge directed that a further hearing be held forthwith at the hospital and directed who should be present (did not specify either patient or his mother, and neither attended nor was consulted). Surgeon and a second treating physician testified to medical need for transfusion. State judge, at guardian ad litem’s request, entered order permitting transfusion. Patient was physically restrained and transfused with three units of packed red blood cells, on afternoon of day of the hearing and order. Patient recovered, without adverse physical reaction from the transfusion, and was discharged one and one-half months later. Subsequently mother initiated this action in federal court, on behalf of her son and for-herself, against the hospital, the risk manager, the surgeon, the second treating physician, and the two hospital attorneys (also sued another physician, but shortly conceded to that physician’s exclusion). The claims were premised on various theories of liability under the Civil Rights Act (1983) and on various state law claims (ultimately dismissed, without determination of the merits, for lack of federal court jurisdiction upon dismissal of all federal law claims). All defendants filed motions for summary judgment in their favor on each of the federal law (civil rights) claims (asserting that no genuine issue of fact existed on the respective claims and theories of action).

Holding Federal trial court sustained all motions for summary judgment in favor of the respective defendants (on the claims of both the patient and the mother), ruling on each claim and theory as follows: 1. As to claim of both patient and mother for breach of constitutional right of noninterference with familial relationship (under fourteenth amendment), held that actions of risk manager (conceded to have been “state actor,” under civil rights law) were not shown to rise to requisite showing of “shocking and egregious conduct” necessary to support a substantive due process violation; and held that procedural due process was not violated for lack of a showing calling into question the emergency need, real or perceived, to forego pre-deprivation motive to the patient or parent, where evidence was that the involved parties all perceived that an emergency existed (distinguished from issue whether, in fact, emergency existed). 2. As to claim of patient for breach of constitutional right of free exercise of religious beliefs (under first amendment), while acknowledging some protection of a minor’s religious freedom, held that parents “can and must” make judgments as to treatment and that parent’s right as to such issue is subject to right of court to order treatment over religious objection, and that thus no substantive due process violation occurred. 3. As to the claim of the patient for breach of constitutional right to direct medical treatment, held that patient, as a minor (even if mature) had no constitutional or common law right to refuse treatment and that guardian ad litem (then “standing in the shoes” of the mother) had consented, and, in any event, the “legal cause” of any such deprivation of right was the order of the court (not a party) and not the actions of the individuals that led up to the order. (Also found no procedural due process violation in lack of notice of the hearing, where the situation was reviewed by three doctors, an impartial judge; and a guardian ad litem.) As to liability of defendants other than the risk manager (assuming that any breach of civil rights had occurred), ruled that no requisite showing , in detail, was made of any conspiratorial conduct (stating that, “at best” only an abuse of state judicial procedures was shown). Declined to retain jurisdiction of the separately asserted claims premised on state law, where the federal law question claims had “dropped out of the lawsuit in its early stages” (dismissing those claims “without prejudice”).

CONTRAST THE PREVIOUS CASE WITH THE FOLLOWING CASE: Nicoleau vs. Brookhaven Memorial Hospital (from Hospital Ethics. 1990. March/April.) The New York Court of Appeals has expanded the individual’s right to refuse lifesaving medical care by ruling that the state could not compel treatment, even if a child’s interests would be harmed by the death of a parent who refused the treatment. Arguments on behalf of saving the child’s life have been accepted in the past by lower courts to force medical care on an unwilling patient, but this new ruling, made on January 18, 1990, makes clear that this tactic could no longer be used. The case that prompted the ruling involved a Long Island woman who had hemorrhaged shortly after giving birth and was given a blood transfusion, a procedure the hospital considered necessary to save her life.· The woman, a thirty-five-year-old Jehovah’s Witness, had objected to the transfusion on religious grounds, and the Court of Appeals ruled that her wishes should have been respected. A lower court had quickly ordered the transfusion without holding a full hearing, and the woman survived. The woman, Denise J. Nicoleau of Moriches, New York, filed a civil lawsuit against Brookhaven Memorial Hospital in Patchogue for rejecting her instructions. The case was the first before the Court of Appeals in which a patient refusing lifesaving treatment was the parent of a minor, and thus it was the first time that the court decided whether a child’s “overriding interest” could be cited to deny the parent’s wishes. In a decision written by Chief Judge Sol Wachtler, the court gave a firm no.

Article: The Jehovah’s Witness and Blood: New Perspectives on an Old Dilemma By Janicemarie K. Vinicky, Martin L. Smith, Russell B. Connors, Jr., and Walter E. Kozachuk Reproduced with permission © The Journal of Clinical Ethics This article was written by Janicemarie K. Vinicky, Martin L. Smith, Russell B. Connors, Jr., and Walter E. Kozachuk in their private capacities. No official support or endorsement by the Clinical Center of the National Institute of Health, the Cleveland Clinic Foundation, or St. Mary Seminary (Cleveland) is intended.

This article presents the case of a Jehovah’s Witness, the mother of a severely retarded man, who required surgery to treat an acute subarachnoid hemorrhage that developed from a cerebral artery aneurysm. The authors present the facts of the case, the ethical issues that arose in its evolution, and the medicoethical decisions that were implemented. The authors further discuss caveats, including their conclusion that a Jehovah’s Witness’s acceptance of death in lieu of blood transfusion is not synonymous with his or her acceptance of permanent disability and total dependency.

Case Study History The patient, a 42-year-old white woman, presented to the emergency room with a severe occipital headache of acute onset, mild dizziness, nausea, and vomiting and, later, diplopia. The headache began while the patient was at a restaurant, and it had become so severe within three hours that she required hospitalization. She denied any head trauma, fever or chills, loss of consciousness, visual symptoms (other than diplopia), dysphasia, dysarthria, or limb weakness.

The patient had an eight-year history of hypertension, which was treated with hydrochlorothiazide. There was no history of transient ischemic attacks, stroke, or migraine headaches. There was no history of transient ischemic attacks, stroke, or migraine headaches. Her family history was negative for aneurysms, stroke, hypertension, and migraine headaches. Her social history revealed that she was married and the mother of three adult children. She was a newly baptized Jehovah’s Witness; her husband, although a Christian, was not a Jehovah’s Witness. She worked full time as a school secretary and her paycheck provided significant proportion of the family’s income. Her husband had an eighth-grade education and worked the second shift in a local laundry, earning minimum wage without benefits. Two daughters were married and living away from home. Her son, age 20, was severely retarded and attended a state day school for the mentally handicapped where he was progressing slowly, having attained a preschool level of self-care. The patient and her husband had arranged to work different shifts in order to maintain their separate incomes and to be available should their son become ill and need parental assistance at home. The son related primarily and preferentially to his mother.

Physical Examination Findings The patient was alert and oriented to person, place, and time. Kernig’s sign was negative, while Brudzinski’s sign was positive. A right VI nerve palsy was present. Her pupils were 4mm and reactive to direct and consensual light, and photophobia was evident. Motor power and tone were normal. DTRs were 2+ and symmetrical, with plantars flexor bilaterally. The remainder of the neurologic exam was normal. General examination was normal except for an S4 heart sound on cardiac auscultation.

Laboratory Findings A computed tomography scan of the head revealed a diffuse subarachnoid hemorrhage with mild ventricular dilation. On angiogram, an aneurysm was evident at the bifurcation of the left internal carotid artery. The results of an initial laboratory evaluation were as follows: hemoglobin, 9.5; hematocrit, 28.8; platelet counts, Z35,000; prothrombin time, 12.4 sec; and partial thromboplastin time, 22.3 sec.

Hospital Course The patient’s labile blood pressure was controlled with a nipride infusion. The medical chart indicated that the patient was a Jehovah’s Witness who refused blood transfusions (“even if it means death”) but was not specific about her willingness to accept autotransfusion or cell-saver therapy; the chart also did not note discussion with the patient regarding specific anticipated risks of the proposed surgery, such as vasospasm and stroke, if blood products were needed but not given. The patient underwent a craniotomy with clipping of the L. anterior cerebral artery aneurysm. A mild right hemiparesis developed the first day after surgery. Angiography revealed cerebral vasospasm. Volume expanders were used, and four days after surgery the patient’s hematocrit was 22.6 and her hemoglobin was 7.5. She developed global aphasia and a complete right hemiparesis. The patient’s husband and sister, neither a Jehovah’s Witness, requested that she be given blood. The attending physicians had determined that transfusion should not be performed because of the patient’s religious beliefs. The patient’s primary intensive care nurse suggested consultation with the hospital ethicist and possibly with the institution’s ethics committee. The patient’s primary caregivers and her husband and family were invited to a multidisciplinary conference. During the discussion it became apparent that the patient’s husband was uncertain of the depth of his wife’s religious convictions. She was a new Witness, having been baptized four months earlier. The patient’s husband “sensed” that his wife found the community support and the social interaction with the church more important than its teachings about blood. Unfortunately, they had never specifically discussed her wishes concerning transfusion. Furthermore, he stated an uncertainty about what treatment course his wife would choose if she knew that failure to transfuse would result in permanent disability. He reported that she had mentioned to both him and her sister (while caring for a cousin in the end stages of cancer) that she wished “never” to become permanently bedridden or unable to communicate. She also frequently expressed a strong and primary commitment to her son, declining invitations to vacation away from him. The primary physician informed the patient’s husband that, without transfusion, his wife’s death was far less likely than permanent disability. Consequently, the patient’s husband found himself attempting to balance his wife’s religious beliefs with a previously expressed wish “never” to become a burden to her family and a strong and freely chosen dedication to their retarded son. The inability of the patient’s surrogate to prioritize his wife’s values left the health care team uncertain about her transfusion refusal. The autonomy dilemma, juxtaposed against the probability that transfusion would reverse some of the patient’s debility, 1* posed a significant ethical quandary.

The Issues The primary ethical issue in this case was whether the physician was obligated to abide by this Jehovah’s Witness’s previously expressed wish not to receive blood, or whether there were factors that would justify overriding her religiously motivated convictions against blood transfusion. There is something both old and new in this case. What is old is the familiar but no less troubling dilemma for health care providers: the obligation to respond to this patient’s medical needs and to do what one can to promote life and, on the other hand, the obligation to respect her previously expressed wishes not to receive blood transfusion. But there are also some new wrinkles in this case that cause one to pause and reexamine the classic dilemma. Does this woman’s relationship with her 20-year-old, severely mentally handicapped son influence whether or not to respect her wishes concerning transfusion? If so, does that relationship make the critical difference, that is, does it ethically justify transfusion? Is an aspect of Christian matrimonial “headship” operative here, namely, does this patient’s husband, himself not a Witness, have the religious authority to override his wife’s wishes concerning transfusion? Are this woman’s previously expressed wishes to accept death rather than blood transfusion synonymous with a willingness to accept a life of permanent disability and dependency on others? In our discussion of this case, we will not only be addressing some of the fundamental issues in cases involving Jehovah’s Witnesses but also the more precise issues raised by this specific case.

We intend to summarize the beliefs of Jehovah’s Witnesses concerning blood and “headship.” We will then offer an ethical analysis of the case in view of its specific circumstances. Finally, we will offer reflections on some insights gained from this case concerning not only Jehovah’s Witnesses, blood, and “headship” but also ethical decision making in the health care setting.

Jehovah’s Witnesses and Blood Jehovah’s Witnesses are a Christian sect founded in the 1870s in Pennsylvania. Their beliefs, based on a literal interpretation of the Bible, include a refusal to acknowledge the authority of earthly powers and a refusal “…to take blood into their system either by eating or by transfusion.”2 These convictions concerning blood are based upon biblical texts that prohibit the taking of blood or drinking of blood by God’s people (Genesis 9:3 and Leviticus 17:13-14). Including this passage from the Acts of the Apostles (15:19-20): “It is my judgement, therefore, that we ought not to cause God’s Gentile converts any difficulties. We should merely write to them to abstain from anything contaminated by idols, from illicit sexual union, from the meat of strangled animals, and from eating blood.” Witnesses do not view these passages as relating merely to dietary or ritual laws. In biblical perspective, blood represents a most sacred life source.3 The biblical laws concerning blood are not peripheral but central to the Witnesses’ faith and are taken with the utmost seriousness: “The issue of blood for Jehovah’s Witnesses, therefore, involves the most fundamental principles on which they as Christians base their lives. Their relationship with their Creator and God is at stake.”2 Because these convictions are at the center of the faith life of Jehovah’s Witnesses, they should be respected by health care personnel. However, as experience bears out, not all Jehovah’s Witnesses interpret this prohibition in the same way. Jonsen4 has identified two questions to which Witnesses are found to give diverse answers: 1) What ae the consequences of violating the prohibition? And 2) To what exactly does the prohibition apply? Violating the prohibition means for some Witnesses the loss of salvation; for others, it is a forgivable sin. Some hold that one who receives blood – regardless of the circumstances – is cut off from the community; others do not take such a stand. Some Witnesses insist that the negative spiritual effects are incurred regardless of whether the person actually chooses the transfusion; others assert that one is not spiritually affected if transfused against one’s will or while unconscious.4 Nonetheless, awareness of this diversity of opinion is not an invitation either to weaken consideration of an individual’s beliefs or to manipulate the patient. Rather, an exploration and an awareness of the beliefs of a particular Jehovah’s Witness should enable attending medical personnel to treat the patient contextually, with understanding and sensitivity to specific needs. To what then, does the prohibition against receiving blood apply? That question, too, yields diverse answers. Witnesses are generally prohibited not only from receiving whole blood but also packed red cells, plasma, white blood cells, and platelets.5 Questions remain, however, concerning dialysis, plasmapheresis, and various forms of autotransfusion.6 Physicians treating Jehovah’s Witnesses would do well to determine in fine detail the types of products and the specific procedures with which the particular patient is comfortable. A physician willing to treat Witnesses on their own terms must keep abreast of the developing body of: “…ancillary means, technical variations and alternatives to standard procedures in order to minimize risks and achieve acceptable results.”7

Jehovah’s Witnesses and Headship Another relevant circumstance in this case is that the patient’s husband was not a Witness but identified himself as a Christian. The Jehovah’s Witness faith tradition places emphasis on the husband/father role of headship, which holds that “the head of every man is the Christ, in turn the head of a woman is the man; in turn the head of Christ is God” (1 Corinthians 11:3). This tradition gives the husband/father authority as the designated head of his family and requires him to 1) recognize Christ as his own head and as his model for behaving as a Christian husband/father; 2) recognize that the “Christ-like” husband/father has been given “priority” over women and is thereby responsible for directing the decisions and worship of his family; and 3) responsibly provide both materially and spiritually for his household.8 This tradition provides that the headship position be revoked when a husband/father engages in “unscriptural conduct” as interpreted by the Jehovah’s Witness faith tradition.9 How do these principles and this concept relate specifically to this case? According to an authoritative Jehovah’s Witness source (Rev. Michael Randolph, Chairman, Greater Washington Jehovah’s Witness Hospital Liaison Committee, Bethesda, MD, 1989), the nonWitness (Christian) head maintains the position only if he authentically represents the wishes of his wife as an autonomous individual following the faith tradition. Conversely a Jehovah’s Witness wife whose husband is a non-Witness urgently requiring blood transfusion is obligated to represent her husband’s wishes and faith tradition and not impose those of the Witness upon him. She should not ask that blood be given to her husband because that is against the law Jehovah; rather, she should express the wishes of her husband to have a blood transfusion if such a request authentically represents his stated wishes. Witnesses are urged to discuss these potentially conflictual situations with their spouses and to respect each other’s stated wishes. Many Witnesses carry a card, a Jehovah’s Witness Transfusion Refusal Card, identifying themselves as such and stating their wish to refuse blood or blood products even when facing death. Because the expressed wishes of this patient and those of her husband appear to be in conflict, the Witnesses interpretation of this request for transfusion on behalf of his wife would likely be that of ”unscriptural conduct,” which would justify removing the husband from his position as head and possibly requiring Jehovah’s Witness elders to step in on the patient’s behalf.

Ethical Analysis In its report entitled Deciding to Forgo Life Sustaining Treatment, 10 the President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research concludes that competent, informed patients have the authority to make their own health care decisions, including those to forgo treatment and allow death to occur. The Hastings Center’s Guidelines on the Termination of Life Sustaining Treatment and the Care of the Dying11 echoes this general principle by affirming patients’ rights to control what happens to their bodies, including the use of life-sustaining treatment. More specific to the case at hand, the Hastings Center’s Guidelines, also assert that among the treatments a patient may choose to forgo is the administration of blood and blood products. These authoritative statements on patient autonomy and treatment refusal are helpful, broad brush stroke guidelines for approaching dilemmas involving conflicts between patient wishes and the health care team’s perception of beneficial treatment. But if ethics and medicine are to avoid the “tyranny of principles,” the uniqueness and particularity of each clinical case must also be considered. Different ethical evaluations can emerge from analyses of cases in which a blood transfusion is refused by a 70-year-old widow who is her own decision maker and by parents on behalf of their 25-year-old, mentally handicapped daughter. Furthermore, differences in the circumstances surrounding blood product refusals by a 25-year-old single woman and a 25-year-old mother of two children under the age of 5 (specific innocent third parties) could lead to different ethical conclusions. Guiding principles (usually abstracted from similar cases) and case specific circumstances must be addressed in the process of arriving at sound medicoethical decisions. The factors to be considered and evaluated in the case at hand were mentioned above and include 1) the 20-year-old dependent, mentally handicapped son (a specific innocent third party), whose life would be significantly affected should death or disability result from his mother’s treatment refusal; 2) the patient’s husband, not a Jehovah’s Witness, who clearly and firmly requested that his wife receive the necessary blood transfusions and who, by Jehovah’s Witness standards, held and consequently relinquished the position of head of his family and marriage; and 3) the informed consent and informed refusal process, which included the patient’s understanding of the risk of death if necessary blood transfusions were not administered intraoperatively but did not include a discussion of the possibility of life with disability if necessary blood transfusions were not provided intraoperatively or post-operatively. Each of these circumstances must be evaluated for ethical relevance and weight. Do any or some combination of these considerations influence the respect usually given the previously expressed wishes of a mentally capacitated patient? Jonsen4 has stated that, as amoral argument, responsibility, to others (innocent third parties) has its perils and is “reprehensible paternalism” when used to override a competent patient’s wishes. In his view, the decision to override the Jehovah’s Witness’s freedom in order to enable the Witness to fulfill responsibilities freely is a contradictory one. Furthermore, Jehovah’s Witnesses live within close, supportive communities, so it is not clear that the care of survivors would fall upon the public. Finally, Jonsen asserts, a physician’s social responsibilities do not weigh so heavily that they override his or her duty to respect the wishes of a particular patient. We agree with Jonsen that restricting patient autonomy on the basis of responsibility to others has its inherent dangers. The ethicist and the clinician should tread on this ground with great caution. Nevertheless, this is ground that at times must be traversed. Throughout their lives, both inside and outside the health care system, individuals freely make choices that place resulting restrictions on their freedom and on present and future options. The decision to have a child, to keep and care for a handicapped infant, and to be educated and employed can all be made freely but nonetheless result in a restriction of one’s freedom. It would be paradoxical and paternalistic but, in our view neither reprehensible nor contradictory to hold someone accountable to responsibilities that have been freely undertaken but that are also inherently restrictive. The argument seems even stronger for restricting autonomy and holding someone accountable when these freely embraced responsibilities are for another person who is dependent upon their fulfillment. Such is the case at hand. The death or significant disability that would result from the patient’s refusal of blood products would prevent her from meeting her freely chosen responsibilities to her son. Jonsen’s two other supporting reasons for his characterization of “reprehensible paternalism” also deserve comment. At root, both call into question the role of the physician as an agent of society, or “gatekeeper,” when fulfillment of that role comes into conflict with the responsibility to honor the patient’s expressed wishes. Jonsen believes that the close-knit nature of such religious communities supports the reasonable expectation that an innocent third part (e.g., a mentally retarded child) will receive appropriate care and will not impose demands on public assistance. This may be a reasonable presumption in many cases, but in this case, not all members of the family unit belonged to this religious group. Community support may not have been as comfortable, continuous, or committed because the primary surviving caregiver was not a community member. Furthermore, we are not concerned simply with the addition of another client to the public resources roll but with the deprivation of parental/maternal nurturance and care that had become familiar to and were expected by the child as a result of 20 years of assistance and rearing. Jonsen is correct that, in the abstract, it is dubious that physicians’ social responsibilities should override their duty to respect the wishes of a particular patient. Nonetheless, the circumstances of this case suggest to us that a given case may contain an accumulation of circumstances that supports a paternalistic action (i.e., the intentional overriding of an individual’s wishes) to provide medical benefit to the patient and promote the personal and social good of someone other than the patient. The second relevant circumstance that must be considered in the ethical analysis of this case is the role of the non-Witness (Christian) husband in the decision-making process. From an ethical perspective, a proxy or surrogate decision maker should make choices consistent with, and reflective of, the patient’s own values, if those values are known to the proxy. But in this case, the surrogate decision maker found himself in a conflictual situation. It appeared, initially, that he was inadequately reflecting, or even ignoring, the religious value system of his wife. The third and final consideration for the case at hand is the process and content of the informed consent and informed refusal. There is general agreement that an ethically sound informed consent process includes active patient participation and physician disclosure of the nature, purpose, risks, benefits, and alternatives of the proposed treatments.12 Dialogic disclosures between physicians and patients allow opportunities for patients to articulate and prioritize their values with reference to the single value the individual places above all others, particularly when forced to choose between values.13 Generally, patients agree to the foreseeable and accompanying pain, discomfort, side effects, and risks (including death) or particular treatments because they value health and biological life above the avoidance of such burdens and risks. However, even though they too value health and biological life, most Jehovah’s Witnesses hold as a greater good their understanding of the will of Jehovah. This unique belief may lead the Jehovah’s Witness to rank values differently that a non-Witness facing similar health care decisions under similar circumstances. In this case, what was the patient’s hierarchy of values of “goods” as she anticipated surgery, with its many foreseeable intraoperative and postoperative complications and risks? From the chart notes it appears that she viewed compliance with the will of the Creator as more important than the avoidance of death. In relation to the judgements of Jehovah concerning blood transfusions, where did this patient rank not just death, but lifelong permanent disability, paralysis, and total dependency? Although the medical directive card states generically that the witness accepts any risk stemming from the refusal of blood transfusions, what individual decision would this Jehovah’s Witness have made had the informed consent process included a discussion of the foreseeable probability of postoperative survival in a dependent, debilitated state? The inability to answer this question with some certainty is significant. The physician’s obligations to respect one of the patient’s previously stated wishes (to choose death over transfusion) is weakened by the presence of a conflicting wish (“not to be a burden”) and the lack of an opportunity for the patient to consider a potential danger that she is implicitly accepting: life with permanent disability.

The Ethical Conclusion The immediate and critical question before the health care team was whether or not to transfuse, an old and familiar dilemma for those called upon to provide treatment to Jehovah’s Witnesses. It is our belief that the circumstances of this case, especially the presence of the dependent, mentally retarded son, as well as the narrow focus of the patient’s informed refusal and her previously expressed with not to burden her family, create a different and new situation that supports a regrettable but justifiable decision to override the patient’s previously expressed wish against blood transfusion. The ethics consultants in this case advised the surgical and intensive care teams that there was strong ethical support for transfusing the patient. We concur with that opinion.

Reflections and Recommendations The Informed Consent Process We concur that the informed consent process should always include a consideration of the religious beliefs of the patient, particularly in cases where the patient’s religious belief system is likely to be an issue in his or her management. With Jehovah’s Witnesses, it is important to discuss the decision not to accept blood in light of the specific and foreseeable risks. If there is a significant difference in prognosis with and without transfusion, the patient should be informed of the increased risk. Furthermore, this risk should be discussed in light of alternatives to transfusion, such as blood conservation devices and volume expanders. During the consent process, patients should be questioned directly about their willingness to accept potential life-long disability. In the case presented here, the risk of stroke and significant physical and mental incapacity was greater than the risk of death. It is important that the Witness be told as clearly as possible what refusal of blood may mean so that he or she may make arrangements for the fulfillment of parental and spousal responsibilities.

Psychosocial Data We strongly recommend a thorough investigation of the psychosocial factors operative in the patient’s life at the initiation of the informed consent process. For a capacitated patient, this process would include a discussion of family and financial responsibilities, the religious convictions and obligations, the patient’s value system, and the prioritization of the patient’s obligations and beliefs. Indeed, there is an endless variety of human situations and unique facts that may influence the health care team’s decisions.

Resources We also recommend that institutions and physicians involved in the care of Jehovah’s Witnesses seek out a Jehovah’s Witness minister or a member of a Jehovah’s Witness Hospital Liaison Committee (currently formalized in many major US cities) for advice in cases such as the one presented. If someone other than the next of kin can more adequately reflect the patient’s religious convictions, such an individual should be consulted in the decision making process. This is not to imply that in every case someone other than the patient’s surrogate should be asked for input on the patient’s depth of conviction, but rather that such consultation becomes appropriate when information is either lacking or unclear. Jehovah’s Witness Hospital Liaison Committees exist to educate physicians and institutional staff members about transfusion refusals and alternative therapies that are acceptable to Jehovah’s Witnesses. Such committees suggest that hospitals develop a registry of physicians willing to care for Witnesses as well as those unwilling to do so. These committees have been instrumental in the transfer of Jehovah’s Witnesses to institutions willing to respect the wishes of the Witness and to provide him or her with the necessary medical/surgical care. Within each hospital the committees are willing to work with institutional ethics committees to formulate policies relating to the care of Jehovah’s Witnesses and to educate Witnesses themselves about alternatives to transfusion and their obligation to be candid with this physician about their religious affiliation. We concur that should an institution develop a policy or practice of transfusing Witnesses under certain circumstances, Jehovah’s Witnesses should be informed of his practice on admission to the institution.

Involvement of Caregivers The term physician-patient relationships would more appropriately be called the team-physicianpatient relationship. Multiple caregivers, including nurses, therapists and technicians, interns, resident physicians, ethicists, social workers, and patient advocates, are directly involved in the care of any one patient. Consequently, it is imperative that primary decision makers include as many care providers as possible when discussing decisions such as transfusion refusals. Anecdotally, there have been cases in which a surgeon accepts a Jehovah’s Witness patient, without consulting the anesthesiologist, who is subsequently reluctant to participate in the patient’s care. To protect the Jehovah’s Witness from such harm and to allow for “conscientious objection” by caregivers, discussions concerning patient management must include all team members involved in the care of any Jehovah’s Witnesses.

Conclusion This article has been written in the hope of contributing to the quality of ethical decision making in cases involving Jehovah’s Witnesses. The case discussed reveals a number of elements important to such decision making. An attentive informed consent and informed refusal process should include a discussion about the risks of not only death but also other potential negative outcomes. Investigation into case-specific circumstances and relevant psychosocial data should include a consideration of innocent third parties. Physician and institutional education concerning the beliefs of Jehovah’s Witnesses (e.g., headship and the various interpretations of the prohibition against blood) may be necessary and fruitful. While these factors – along with communication among health care team members, the patient, and his or her family may not simplify health care relating to Jehovah’s Witnesses, they will help to ensure that such decisions are ethically responsible and appropriate.

Article: Commentary – Jehovah’s Witnesses and Blood By Albert R. Jonsen The article by Vinicky et al, is an excellent example of clear, sound case ethics analysis. I have a quarrel only with its title. The authors do present a new perspective, but the “old” problem of caring for the Jehovah’s Witness who refuses blood is not a dilemma. A dilemma, Webster’s tells us, is “a choice between evenly balanced alternatives; a predicament defying satisfactory solutions.” The problem posed to health professionals when a competent adult patient refuses recommended and necessary treatment may be agonizing, perplexing, and aggravating, but it is not a problem without a satisfactory solution and the alternative choices are not evenly balanced. It is clear, from ethical discussion and legal decisions, that such a patient has the right to refuse treatment and that providers have a duty to draw back. It is equally clear that the minor child of Jehovah’s Witness parents should be provided necessary medical treatment. I am sure that the authors would not cavil at my disagreement with their title. They would probably willingly correct it. I suspect that what they intended to convey was that they had a new and interesting case that illustrates a familiar, though difficult ethical problem. Indeed, in citing with approval my own article on this problem, they seem to believe that the apparent dilemma or conflict between beneficence and autonomy should be resolved in favor of the patient’s choice, regardless of its medical inadvisability. They affirm the principles that support this position. Then, they present a case and a solution with which they suggest I might disagree, on the basis of the principles. They write, “We agree with Jonsen that restricting patient autonomy on the basis of responsibility to others has its inherent dangers. The ethicist and the clinician should tread on this ground with great caution. Nevertheless, this is ground that at times must be traversed.” They might be surprised to learn that I have no argument with their “nevertheless.” Indeed, I fully endorse not only their “nevertheless” but also their resolution of the case they present. The reason for my enthusiastic approval is that Vinicky et al. present a fine piece of casuistry. They affirm their casuistical bent by stating that “if ethics and medicine are to avoid the ‘tyranny of principles’, the uniqueness and particularity of each clinical case must also be considered… Guiding principles (usually abstracted from similar cases) and case specific circumstances must be addressed in the process of arriving at sound medicoethical decisions.” I have publicly proclaimed myself a casuist and vigorously promote casuistry as the method for clinical ethics. Their phrase “tyranny of principles” was coined by Stephen Toulmin, my coauthor on The Abuse of Casuistry. Casuistry is the analysis of moral issues in light of the circumstances of cases. Casuistry appreciates the importance of general rules and maxims of morality but recognizes that they hold true with certainty only in typical conditions and circumstances. The competent and informed adult Jehovah’s Witness who will die without transfusion represents a typical case (typical here does not necessarily mean most frequent, but a case representing essential features of a class). This type of case is, in essence, a case of competent refusal and, as such, is ruled by the principle of autonomy. As cases depart from that type, they require modifications of that resolution that respect the peculiar circumstances. Some circumstances will not force any modifications, as they represent trivial or irrelevant features of the case. Others immediately strike us as significant and give rise to the impression that we have a difficult case and possibly an apparent dilemma. Vinicky et al. present a case in which two circumstances are striking. First, the patient in need of blood is a woman with a 20-year-old retarded son who is dependent on her and to whom she is devoted. Second, the patient does not need blood to survive but rather to avoid the devastating effects of a subarachnoid hemorrhage. She will not die but will probably survive with severe deficits. Both of these circumstances deserve special attention. The first forces us to wonder whether we ought to look differently in this case at the rationale that would allow care providers to override a treatment refusal because of the problems a parent’s death creates for children and society. The authors argue that we should, and I agree. The second unusual circumstance is that the use of blood is here not a life-saving procedure, as in the typical Jehovah’s Witness case, but a disability preventing procedure. We are told that current opinion in neurology advises that “neurologic deficits produced by ischemia secondary to vasospasm are potentially reversible if blood flow can be restored before permanent neurologic deficits occur.” If this is so, it suggests that administration of blood might prevent permanent impairment that could render this patient a long-lived invalid. It is far from clear that this situation has been envisioned by the person who adopts the tenets of the Jehovah’s Witnesses. It is not, to my knowledge, discussed in the Witnesses’ explanation of their doctrine. Indeed, they prohibit the “taking or drinking of blood” (interpreted to include transfusion) quite absolutely and unconditionally. Thus, it might be fairly assumed that they have considered the problem of life with continued disabilities and still ruled out transfusion. However, this assumption does not reflect the usual approach to moral issues taken by fundamentalist groups. Fundamentalism (admittedly difficult to define) usually means that moral teachings are communicated in very absolute terms without any casuistry of exceptions and excuses. God’s word is, for the fundamentalist, a clear and definitive “yea or nay.” Thus, it is unlikely that adherents of fundamentalist beliefs are well informed or have seriously reflected on the exceptional circumstances. Even this patient’s words – “even if it means death” – can be interpreted as the rote expression of the absolute belief, rather than a reflective statement about her options short of death. Indeed, even an elder of the church if faced with this situation, might “forgive,” even if he could not permit or tolerate. It is not unfair, then, that others such as her husband and the physicians, might reasonably presume that this patient would accept blood when faced with two circumstances together: her life-long disability and her dependent retarded son. In my opinion, the authors have reached a sound, justifiable ethical conclusion in this case. Casuistry is perilous (as is the moral life in general). Its sound conclusions can slip into shaky realizations. Its careful attention to exceptions can become a careless opening of loopholes. Casuistry is closely allied to conscience: The good casuist is not a clever sophist but one who comes to cases with a sincere commitment to broad, moral imperatives, such as the respect for autonomy and, at the same time, a sensitivity to those conditions that might qualify that commitment in the name of some other equally moral purpose. I can, then, maintain the position I expressed in my article on Jehovah’s Witnesses and blood, namely that the competent adult Witness should not be transfused against his or her expressed wishes, and, at the same time, that this incompetent adult Witness, in these circumstances, should be transfused. This is not a dilemma or a paradox; it is good casuistry and, in my opinion, good clinical ethics.

Article: Commentary – Response from Jehovah’s Witnesses By Nathanael A. Reed Vinicky and coauthors, in agreeing with the ethics committee that a transfusion was justified, express the opinion that “the argument seems even stronger for restricting autonomy and holding someone accountable when these freely embraced responsibilities are for another person who is dependent upon their fulfillment.” This position is, indeed, regrettably, but it clearly is not justified. The primary focus must remain on patient autonomy – the right of the competent person to choose or not to choose the medical treatment recommended by physicians, including whether or not to accept blood. Moreover, the authors would have us believe that only blood could save the patient from serious disability. Furthermore, they have not mentioned at all the risks to health and life to which one is subjected in receiving a blood transfusion. More to the point, what the authors reveal by their reasoning in this case is how lightly they have taken the deep moral and religious convictions of this God-fearing woman. Because of her wish to obey God’s law on blood, as well as to avoid the obvious medical dangers of blood, she has become, in their eyes, one who no longer makes rational decisions. She has been blinded by religious fanaticism. But by what authority would they have the members of the ethics committee impose their lack of respect for divine law on others? Despite the clear statements of this Witness patient that a transfusion should not be given under any circumstances, the authors postulate that if she had been able to review the possibility of being critically disabled and of not being able to care for her dependent retarded son, it might reasonably be presumed that she would agree to accept blood. Therefore, they felt justified in overruling the patient’s autonomy. The authors evidently would have us accept the premise that the responsibility of a parent who freely chooses when she brings a child into the world also includes the requirement that she not do anything that puts her life or health in serious jeopardy. Following this reasoning, why not force (not just advise) pregnant woman to quit smoking, stop taking drugs, or forgo any other activities that would jeopardize their health. Situation ethics is never justified, and that is true in this case. What mental trauma, what psychological anguish and trial the authors and the ethics committee would impose upon this woman for the remained of her life if she came to learn that she had been transfused with blood against her wishes! Surely, it is the height of presumption to conclude that she as a wife and mother did not give serious and profound thought to how her possible death or crippling disability would affect her handicapped son when she said she did not want blood under any circumstances. Could she not be doing just that by refusing blood? Blood can kill; it also can cause crippling disability! She wanted to live, not to die or be disabled from hepatitis or AIDS or a host of other things that can be caused from a transfusion. How would the physicians and members of the ethics committee feel if she were given a transfusion and then died because of it? Where would this leave the handicapped son? Her decision to refuse blood need by no means reflect a lack of love or concern for her on or members of her family. Jehovah’s Witnesses are noted for the love they have within the family. The Bible, the Word of God, teaches the importance of loving one’s family and caring well for family responsibilities. But the Bible also shows the seriousness of disobeying God’s laws, including the one that prohibits the use of another’s blood to sustain one’s own life (Genesis 9:3, 4; Acts 15:19-21). Obedience to God’s laws not only contributes to good health now (remaining free from AIDS, venereal diseases, immoderate lifestyles, etc.) but ensures God’s favorable judgement as to everlasting in a cleansed “new earth” (Revelation 21:1-5). The patient made unqualified statements that she did not want a blood transfusion under any circumstances. Her earlier executed medical document clearly directed that “no blood transfusions be given to me, even though my physicians deem such vital to my health or life” (Figure 1 is a facsimile of this document). When she entered the hospital, the physical examination found her “alert and oriented to person, place, and time.” We assume the patient later became unable to express her wishes clearly. But becoming incapacitated does not render invalid the medical document she executed. In this document, she covered the contingency that she might lose consciousness by authorizing one of two signing witnesses to see that her decision to refuse blood was upheld. While the hospital chart did not “note discussion regarding specific anticipated risks of the proposed surgery such as vasospasm and possible stroke if blood products were needed but not given,” what did they discuss with the patient while she was able to make her own decisions? It is reasonable to assume that at least the general risks were discussed, including the possibility of being disabled. Was there a discussion of the risks of blood transfusions? If they did not discuss these risks with her clearly, then that would be negligence on their part. Nevertheless, her chart clearly reflects that she did not want a transfusion, “even if it means death.” The authors also gave weight to an incidental statement that the patient allegedly made to her husband while caring for a cousin in the end stages of cancer, that she “never” wanted to become permanently bedridden or unable to communicate. No one in his or her right mind would even want this. But are we to assume from this very natural and human statement that she would want to compromise the principles by which she lived, so important to her that she would be willing to die for them, in order to avoid this debilitation? While the primary physician “informed the patient’s husband that without transfusion the likelihood of his wife’s death was far less probably than permanent disability,” the fact is that this was an opinion. Physicians are not infallible. The authors provide references to the medical literature to suggest the “probability of reversal of some of the patient’s debility with transfusion.” It is of interest that only one of these medical studies (published in 1981) suggests that a transfusion might be helpful in treating vasospasm associated with subarachnoid hemorrhage and that this recommendation is only one of several alternatives. Moreover, the latest medical literature puts the emphasis, not on giving blood, but on carefully controlled hemodilution and selected drug therapy in treating this condition.1-4 Jehovah’s Witnesses ask for alternatives to blood and invariably find physicians who treat them just as effectively without giving blood. The authors report that the attending physicians had determined that transfusion, while recommended, was not justified because of the patient’s religious faith. The physicians decided correctly. They are to be commended. They should not have been dissuaded from their decision by the recommendation of the ethics committee. While we are not told of the patient’s present condition, we hope that she has recovered from her disability without having to endure the terrible psychological effects of having had a blood transfusion forced upon her. Appendix At the Brooklyn headquarters of the Jehovah’s Witnesses, the Department of Hospital Information Services [(718) 625-3600] gives assistance in locating physicians who will treat patients without giving blood transfusions. In more than 100 major US cities, communities or trained personnel are available to assist Witness patients in talking with physicians and hospital personnel when problems arise. Invariably, they are able to defuse confrontation and help with solutions. These professionals, accessible through the elders of any congregation can call the Brooklyn office at any time on a 24-hour line for assistance in managing a case. Often a search of current medical literature and consultation with medical specialists will produce alternative ways of treating the patient without blood. The full text of the medical document of Jehovah’s Witness appears in Figure 1. A new card is personally filled out yearly and is thus a current expression of each one wishes.

JEHOVAH’S WITNESS: Discussion Questions 1. The basic issue in the treatment of Jehovah’s Witnesses is not one of medicine vs. the Bible; rather, it is an issue of informed consent. 2. Is there committee agreement about the consultation by a physician not involved in the patient’s care? 3. Does your hospital have in place a policy regarding emergency care of members of Jehovah’s Witness? Have you reviewed the policy and found it adequate? 4. Regarding children of Witnesses, does the draft policy sound paternalistic in a bad sense its refusal to acknowledge developing autonomy in children?

Further Readings Ackerman, Terence F. 1980. “The Limits of Beneficence; Jehovah Witnesses and Childhood Cancer.” 10: 13-18. Davis, Dena D. 1994. “Does ‘No’ Mean ‘Yes’? The Continuing Problem of Jehovah Witnesses and Refusal of Blood Products.” Second Opinion: 35-42. “How Can Blood Save Your Life?” 1990. Watch Tower Bible and Tract Society of Pennsylvania.

in article 16 case study 1 sue refused

Thomas Law Offices

Have You Been Injured? We're Ready to Fight for You.

What Is Article 16 in a Personal Injury Action?

What Is Article 16 in a Personal Injury Action

A personal injury case—when one party pursues legal action after being harmed by the negligence or wrongdoing of another party—may be impacted by the terms of Article 16.

Let’s look at exactly what Article 16 is in a personal injury action. If you have questions related to your case, the experienced personal injury attorneys of Thomas Law Offices can help. Our firm represents clients filing injury claims after suffering harm caused by others. We have nationwide experience and are highly educated and practiced in the varying laws that govern civil cases in different states across the country.

Table of Contents

What Is Article 16?

Article 16, part of New York state’s Civil Practice Law & Rules (CPLR), discusses Limited Liability of Persons Jointly Liable . It was added to the CPLR in 1966.

The addition of this section was an important moment in the state’s legal history. This is because it addressed in clear terms what happens when more than one party is liable for the plaintiff’s injuries.

Most people think of personal injury cases as involving two parties: the plaintiff (the injured party) and the defendant (the party being accused of causing the injury). But many cases involve multiple defendants, and Article 16 governs those situations.

How Does Article 16 Affect a Personal Injury Case?

Before Article 16 was added, New York civil law did not have the means to effectively handle personal injury cases involving more than one liable party. So any one party found to be at fault could be made to pay the full amount of compensation owed to the injured victim—even if there were other involved parties who contributed to causing the incident.

Under the terms of Article 16, however, liability can be divided between multiple parties. If a judge and jury find more than one party to be responsible for the plaintiff’s injuries, a percentage of fault can be assigned to each, and the amount they must pay to the victim will align with their assigned percentage.

Article 16 stipulates that:

  • If a party is 50% or more liable, the plaintiff can seek full compensation from them.
  • If a party is less than 50% liable, they can only be required to pay damages in the amount of their percentage of fault.

So, for example, a victim of medical malpractice may pursue a personal injury action against their care team, which involves multiple doctors, nurses, and other medical professionals.

A physician or other care provider may be found to be mostly (more than half) at fault for all the losses the patient suffered. The injured plaintiff has the right to seek maximum compensation for the full extent damages from that party.

But there may also be lesser-involved aides, technicians, nurses, or assistants who partially (but not chiefly) contributed to the injury incident. If one of these parties is determined to be 20% at fault, for example, they may be required to pay 20% of the compensation owed to the victim.

Does Article 16 Cover All Kinds of Damages?

No, Article 16 does not cover all types of damages. There are limitations on how Article 16 applies in a personal injury action. Primarily, Article 16 does not cover economic damages such as hospital bills, lost wages, or out-of-pocket expenses.

Instead, Article 16 applies to noneconomic damages . While economic damages usually come from tangible bills, noneconomic damages are the losses stemming from non-financial causes. They often include:

  • Pain and suffering
  • Mental anguish
  • Emotional distress
  • Lowered quality of life
  • Loss of enjoyment of life
  • Reputational damage
  • Inconvenience
  • Loss of consortium
  • Permanent disability
  • Disfigurement

These and other noneconomic damages are covered under Article 16. Economic damages are not. Additionally, Article 16 does not apply to property damage claims or cases involving wrongful death.

Can the Plaintiff Also Be Partially at Fault?

Yes, the New York Civil Practice Law & Rules and statutes in many other states recognize that a plaintiff may have in some way contributed to their own injuries. This legal theory is known as “comparative negligence” or “comparative fault.” It means that fault can be shared between the defendant(s) and the person filing the legal claim.

You will need to consult with your personal injury attorney to see if comparative fault laws apply in the state where you are filing your claim or lawsuit. Some states only allow you to file a claim if you are less than 50% at fault for your own injuries.

Many states with comparative fault laws divide or reduce compensation by percentage of fault. For example, in these states, if you are found to be 10% liable for the incident that caused your injuries, your compensation amount will be reduced accordingly by 10%.

Get Qualified, Experienced Legal Help With Your Personal Injury Case

One thing we know for sure is that personal injury laws are complicated. Legislation is always changing, and there are often vast differences in the way civil disputes are handled from state to state.

That’s why lawyers go to school for years and practice for decades to become good at what they do—and why most injured victims know they need to look for professional help handling their case.

We have your back. If you were injured, we have the legal knowledge to get you justice. Contact us today for a free consultation. Our Chicago injury lawyers will assess your legal options with you and guide you to the outcome you’re looking for.

Available 24/7 Free Case Review

Thomas Law Offices Overview Video

Latest Articles

Thomas Law Offices

Free Case Evaluation

At Thomas Law Offices, our personal injury attorneys recognize that our potential clients are likely going through some of the most difficult times of their lives. We don't want you to have to worry about paying out of pocket for legal advice when you're just starting to learn your legal rights and options. That's why we provide free case evaluations. We'll offer our expert advice about your potential case and walk you through how we can help you.

Meet Our Founder

Tad Thomas - Trial Lawyer

Managing Partner

Tad Thomas has dedicated his practice to representing plaintiffs in various types of civil litigation, including personal injury, business litigation, class actions, and multi-district litigation.

After graduating with his law degree in 2000 from Salmon P. Chase College of Law at Northern Kentucky University, Mr. Thomas immediately opened his own private practice and began representing injury victims.

In 2011, Thomas Law Offices was established in Louisville, Kentucky. Over the past decade, Mr. Thomas has expanded his firm and now has offices in three additional locations: Cincinnati, Ohio, Columbia, Missouri, and Chicago, Illinois. He is also a frequent lecturer on topics like trial skills and ethics and technology.

Legal & Firm News

Apr 16, 2024, where do car accidents happen most often in chicago.

As someone who lives in or has traveled through Chicago, you likely don’t need any reminding of how congested our city’s roadways are. This heavy traffic often leads to collisions, which cause motorists to suffer serious injuries and lose their lives. While you’re likely aware of where some of our city’s crash-prone roadways are if […]

Apr 10, 2024

Learn how to protect your loved ones with my nursing home abuse guide.

Thomas Law Offices has over a decade of experience helping families seek justice on behalf of loved ones who have been abused, neglected, or otherwise harmed in nursing homes and long-term care facilities around the nation. Tad Thomas himself has spoken multiple times on live TV about the work our firm does and the changes […]

One Year Since Old National Bank Shooting, Co-Counsel Representing Survivors, Families Release Statement

LOUISVILLE, KY – Today, Thomas Law Offices, Everytown Law, and Romanucci & Blandin, who together represent survivors as well as families who lost loved ones in the mass shooting at Old National Bank in Louisville on April 10, 2023, released the following statement: “April 10th marks one year since the tragic mass shooting at the […]

Tad Thomas on The National Crime Victim Bar Association

Turner’s Insurmountable Burden: A Three-Circuit Survey of Prisoner Free Speech Claims

Kristen Schnell , J.D. Candidate 2022, Columbia Law School; B.A. 2018, University of California, Los Angeles.

Turner ’s Insurmountable Burden: A Three-Circuit Survey of Prisoner Free Speech Claims

By Kristen Schnell [1] *

The last case in which the Supreme Court struck down a prison regulation for violating the federal Constitution was the landmark case of  Turner v. Safley , handed down nearly thirty-five years ago.  Turner  also marked the first time the Court established a clear standard to evaluate all such constitutional challenges to prison policies and regulations. As the Court built deference to prison officials into the  Turner  standard, and has issued little guidance as to interpretation of the evidentiary standard in the decades since, circuit courts have been left the weighty task of filling in the jurisprudential gaps. This dearth of guidance is especially troubling in the context of First Amendment free speech restrictions, which impinge on the ability of prisoners to communicate with legal counsel and loved ones. Constraints on face-to-face communication stemming from the COVID-19 pandemic have only further highlighted the importance of written communication and access to printed publications in the prison environment.

Deficiencies in the  Turner  standard (and prisoner-led litigation generally) have been discussed at length by prominent scholars in the criminal justice field. This Note builds on existing scholarship by reviewing roughly fifteen years of circuit court case law in which the standard is applied. Because  Turner  challenges rarely come before the Supreme Court, this review offers valuable insight as to how lower courts typically dispense with prisoners’ free speech claims, and identifies several evidentiary innovations that are worth exploration and adoption by sister circuits. In addition to these evidentiary reforms, which could be adopted unilaterally by lower courts, this Note offers large-scale reforms that could be undertaken by the Supreme Court and Congress.

Table of Contents

Introduction 125

I. Development and Application of the Turner “Reasonableness” Standard 127

A. Pre- Turner Case Law: Martinez Through Wolfish 131

B. Turner v. Safley ’s “Reasonableness” Standard 140

C. Post- Turner : The Court’s Subsequent Free Speech Case Law 143

II. Turner in the Circuit Courts 146

A. Third Circuit 147

B. Fifth Circuit 150

C. Ninth Circuit 153

D. Commonalities and Splits Among the Circuits 155

1. Commonality: Routine Deference 155

2. Circuit Split: Treatment of Incoming Legal Mail 157

3. Circuit Split: Treatment of Outgoing Personal Mail 159

III. Balancing Deference and Constitutional Protections 160

A. Small-Scale Reforms 160

1. Adoption of Bright-Line Evidentiary Rules for Certain Turner Claims 161

2. Barring of Post Hoc Reasoning 162

B. Large-Scale Reforms 164

1. Resolution of Circuit Splits 165

2. Creating a Statutory Cause of Action for Prisoners’ Free Speech Claims 167

Conclusion 169

Introduction

Although the Supreme Court has repeatedly declared that “prison walls do not form a barrier separating inmates from protections of the Constitution,” the Court has erected a barrier of its own through jurisprudence. [2] As a result of the Court’s landmark decision in Turner v. Safley , [3] challenges to prison regulations alleged to violate the Constitution are subject to a standard of review that places a heavy evidentiary burden on the inmate-plaintiff. [4] The Supreme Court has provided little guidance as to what evidence is sufficient to prove that a challenged prison regulation is arbitrary or overreaching, [5] leaving circuit courts to develop disparate standards or none at all. [6] The lack of a clear “roadmap” to success offered by circuit courts has made it difficult for pro se litigants and practitioners to challenge suspect prison regulations in the face of significant judicial deference to prison officials’ judgment. [7]

First Amendment challenges to prison regulations are often heavily fact-dependent and therefore especially unlikely to succeed under Turner ’s deferential standard. [8] Although Congress carved out an exception for First Amendment free exercise challenges—creating a statutory cause of action for these claims that requires heightened scrutiny—free speech challenges must still be brought under Turner ’s “reasonableness” standard of review. [9] This lax protection of prisoners’ First Amendment free speech rights is particularly striking when compared to the strict scrutiny review applied to free speech challenges among the general public. [10] As a result of Turner , expansive bans on books, newspapers, correspondence, and other reading materials have been consistently upheld as “reasonably related” to broad goals of “security” or “rehabilitation.” [11] These restrictions often make news headlines for their seemingly arbitrary application, such as a regulation in Ohio that banned a biology book due to nudity, or a federal prison in Colorado that prevented a prisoner from receiving a copy of Barack Obama’s autobiography over “national security” concerns. [12] Advocates have likened First Amendment free speech litigation to “the game Whac-a-Mole”: as soon as one unlawful prison regulation falls, more are enacted in different jurisdictions. [13]

This Note surveys opinions of the Third, Fifth, and Ninth Circuits to examine how circuit courts are formulating the evidentiary burden under Turner and the likelihood of plaintiffs’ claims succeeding under those frameworks. [14] The circuit courts’ significant deference to the state, regardless of how the evidentiary burden was formulated, highlights the need for reforms to evidentiary requirements in order to help curb excessive judicial deference under Turner . Part I traces the development of the Turner standard of review, provides an overview of the Turner standard itself, and discusses subsequent case law that dictates when and how Turner is applied in the context of free speech case claims. [15] Part II details circuit court interpretations of the evidentiary burden required under Turner , resulting from a survey of prisoner free speech jurisprudence from 2006 to late 2020. Finally, Part III discusses possible reforms to these disparate standards to increase the likelihood of success for prison regulation challenges.

I. Development and Application of the Turner “Reasonableness” Standard

For nearly two centuries after the United States’ founding, prisoners were considered “slaves of the State,” [16] outside the bounds of constitutional protection. [17] The only protections granted to prisoners could be found in state law, should a state choose to afford them. [18] During this period, federal courts largely refused to consider the merits of claims brought by prisoner-plaintiffs, an approach that came to be known as the “hands-off” doctrine. [19] Courts were reluctant to “subvert prison discipline” and believed they lacked the expertise of officials maintaining prisons and jails, rendering them ill-suited to rule on challenges to conditions of confinement or treatment of prisoners. [20] Courts also feared overstepping the separation of powers, as operation and funding of correctional facilities are creatures of the legislative and executive branches, rather than the judicial branch. [21]

Beginning in the 1950’s, prison riots became a regular occurrence, often due to inadequate treatment and conditions of confinement. [22] The need for reform gradually drove the Warren Court to shift away from their “hands-off” approach and rule on the merits of prisoners’ rights claims, directly addressing the unconstitutionality of prison conditions and treatment of prisoners. [23] Despite the increase of judicial review in the mid-to-late 1960’s, growth in the U.S. prison population over the next decade furthered existing tension in penal institutions. Beginning in 1972, the rate of U.S. imprisonment grew dramatically, with annual increases in the prison population of six to eight percent. [24] Prison administrators faced the difficult task of maintaining order in institutions with immense overcrowding, which contributed to increases in violence and difficulty maintaining adequate supervision of prisoners. [25] Another wave of litigation followed, again challenging conditions of confinement and inmate treatment. [26]

Early lawsuits during this second wave of litigation revealed that prison officials frequently could not justify or even explain their procedures, leading courts to call for reforms. [27] Consent decrees that professionalized and bureaucratized corrections management, along with written prison regulations, emerged as the principal remedies. [28] Written regulations served the dual purpose of providing courts with a benchmark for evaluating prison conditions and a guide for prison officials trying to avoid further lawsuits. [29] It quickly became clear, however, that regulations themselves, although initially considered beneficial by courts and reformists, tended to impinge on prisoners’ other fundamental, constitutional rights. [30] Courts thus faced the difficult question of how to “discharge their duty to protect [inmates’] constitutional rights,” [31] while still affording appropriate deference to the judgment of newly “professionalized” prison administrators as to what regulations were truly necessary to maintain safe prison environments. [32]

Inmates’ First Amendment free speech claims were among the first challenges to prison regulations reviewed by the Supreme Court. [33] Outside of prison walls, any restriction or regulation of speech that is based on content is presumptively unconstitutional, [34] and is only justified if the government can prove that the restriction on speech is narrowly tailored to serve compelling state interests, i.e., if it survives strict scrutiny. [35] For content-neutral speech restrictions, the Court still applies intermediate scrutiny, requiring the state or federal government to show that the restriction is narrowly tailored to serve an important or substantial government interest and that alternative means of communication exist. [36] Content-neutral restrictions are often referred to as “time, place, and manner” regulations, as they restrict when, where, and how speech can be expressed, but do not prohibit speech based on the content of the communication. [37] A classic example would be a city ordinance preventing the use of megaphones in a park. The use of strict and intermediate scrutiny to review First Amendment free speech claims is consistent with the Court’s position that where a regulation impinges on fundamental rights, less deference is owed to the state. [38] For the same reason, review for both content-based and “time, place, manner” restrictions places the burden of proof on the state when the constitutionality of regulations affecting speech is challenged. [39]

Despite the Supreme Court’s broad protection of First Amendment free speech rights among the general public by means of heightened scrutiny, the Court has been far more lenient in prison settings, primarily citing the need for deference to prison officials. [40] From 1974 to 1984, the Court took up a string of free speech challenges involving regulations that restricted inmate mail, communication with press, and incoming books, magazines, and news. [41] The “compelling interest” and “substantial interest” standards for public speech restrictions were gradually turned on their head when applied to prison regulations, culminating in a standard of review under Turner v. Safley [42] that asks whether prison regulations that impinge on constitutional rights are reasonably related to a legitimate government interest. [43] Under Turner , the burden of proof also rests with the inmate-plaintiff, who, in contrast to free speech challenges among the public, must overcome a presumption of constitutionality as to the challenged regulation. [44]

As a result of this case law, prisoners’ First Amendment free speech challenges, which already face significant statutory hurdles and adverse judicial doctrines, [45] stand little chance of succeeding on the merits under Turner . Communication and access to information, fundamental American rights, are therefore heavily restricted in prisons and jails with little recourse for affected inmates. The following subsection traces the development of the Turner standard, which is based primarily on First Amendment free speech jurisprudence.

A. Pre- Turner Case Law: Martinez Through Wolfish

In Procunier v. Martinez , [46] the Supreme Court began its decade-long struggle to find an appropriate standard of review for constitutional challenges to prison regulations. [47] Martinez involved a First Amendment free speech challenge to California Department of Corrections (“CDC”) regulations that censored incoming and outgoing personal letters. [48] The restrictions were content-based, specifically prohibiting statements that were critical of a prison administration or deemed “inflammatory,” [49] and reflected the CDC’s general policy toward prisoner mail, which considered the sending and receiving of mail an inmate privilege, not a right. [50] Federal appellate and district courts, including the district court in Martinez , had struggled with the applicability of First Amendment rights to prison inmates for a number of years. [51]

According to the district court in Martinez , the majority of recent cases had adopted a standard of review formulated by the District Court for the Southern District of New York in a case called Carothers v. Follette . [52] The Carothers standard required that any regulation or practice that restricts the right of prisoners’ free expression be “related both reasonably and necessarily to the advancement of some justifiable purpose of imprisonment.” [53] A few other courts, in contrast, had required that the state show a compelling interest for the restriction, as they would with regulations that burdened speech among the general public. [54]

The Supreme Court, however, rejected the district court’s framing of the issue, finding that an inquiry into the applicability of First Amendment rights to prison inmates was unnecessary. [55] Martinez presented a “narrower basis of decision,” namely the rights of inmates’ correspondents, who enjoyed full constitutional protections. [56] The Court identified the First Amendment interest of non-prisoner correspondents as an interest in uncensored correspondence, grounded in the First Amendment’s guarantee of freedom of speech and the derivative First and Fourteenth Amendment protections against “unjustified governmental interference with . . . intended communication[s].” [57] Having adopted that framing, the Court turned to the question of an appropriate standard of review.

The prison regulations at issue in Martinez sought to restrict inmates’ speech, rather than their correspondents’ speech, meaning the restriction on non-prisoner correspondents’ communication was purely incidental. [58] To develop an appropriate standard of review, the Court looked to prior case law where government regulations had resulted in incidental restrictions on speech among the general public, [59] deciding to modify the standard of review applied in those cases to the prison environment. [60] This adapted standard of review called for strict scrutiny, and, as the incidental restriction on speech was content-based, the Court struck down the regulation. [61] Because this standard was developed solely to determine the extent of non-prisoner correspondents’ rights, however, the extent of prisoners’ First Amendment rights after Martinez remained unclear .

The Court faced the standard of review question for a second time that term in the case of Pell v. Procunier . [62] Pell again raised a First Amendment free speech challenge against the California Department of Corrections, brought by both California prison inmates and professional journalists. [63] The regulations at issue in this case only allowed journalists to speak with randomly-selected inmates, rather than specifically-selected inmates, out of prison officials’ concerns that its previous “laissez-faire” policy regarding inmate interviews had led to an increase in disciplinary problems. [64] As opposed to Martinez , the Court squarely addressed the First Amendment rights of prisoners, holding that:

[A] prison inmate retains those First Amendment rights that are not inconsistent with his status as a prisoner or with the legitimate penological objectives of the corrections system. Thus, challenges to prison restrictions that are asserted to inhibit First Amendment interests must be analyzed in terms of the legitimate policies and goals of the corrections system . . . . [65]

The Court thereby settled the issue that lower courts had been debating since at least 1968, [66] choosing to adopt a standard of review for First Amendment rights similar to the Carothers “reasonable and necessary” formulation from the Southern District of New York. [67] Simply stated, the question for courts after Pell became whether a challenged regulation impinging upon First Amendment rights was “reasonably and necessarily” related to legitimate policies and goals of the corrections system, a more lax formulation of rational basis review. [68]

Turning to the facts of the case, the Court first identified the “legitimate penal objectives” in Pell as deterrence of crime via isolation of the prisoner, rehabilitation, and the “central” correctional goal of security. [69] To determine the extent of the burden placed on prisoner communication by the regulation, the majority also considered the alternative means of personal communication afforded to prisoners. [70] Such available alternatives included visits from friends, family, and legal counsel, and also communication by letter (which the Court noted was recently safeguarded by its decision in Procunier v. Martinez ). [71]

Given the availability of these alternative means of communication, and the apparent content-neutral operation of the rule, the Court held that, on balance, the regulation was not overly burdensome, but rather was consistent with rules and regulations to which “prisoners necessarily are subject.” [72] The Court further held that determining the appropriate means to accomplish legitimate penological objectives, such as security in this case, is a matter of corrections officials’ expertise. [73] Absent “substantial evidence” in the record to suggest that officials have exaggerated their response to such legitimate interests, courts therefore owed deference to officials in their determinations. [74] Although security and other penological considerations in this case would not reasonably support a complete ban on inmate expression or communication, the Court held that the prison officials’ security considerations were “sufficiently paramount” to justify the regulation restricting inmates’ at-will access to press. [75]

Three years later, the Supreme Court considered a First Amendment prison regulation challenge for a third time. In the case of Jones v. North Carolina Prisoners’ Labor Union, Inc ., [76] a prisoners’ union brought suit after North Carolina Department of Correction regulations “prohibited inmates from soliciting other inmates to join [the Union], barred all meetings of the Union, and refused to deliver packets of Union publications that had been mailed in bulk to several inmates for redistribution among other prisoners.” [77] The prisoner-plaintiffs alleged these practices violated their First Amendment rights of free speech and association. [78] The Department of Correction, for its part, alleged that the very existence of the union would increase administrative burdens and feared the inmates would undermine security by forming a power bloc via the Prisoners’ Labor Union. [79]

While the Supreme Court had decided Pell in the context of First Amendment free speech rights, Jones dealt with the novel issue of prisoners’ First Amendment right to assembly. [80] The Supreme Court was critical of the lower court’s decision in favor of the union on this claim, [81] asserting that the court “got off on the wrong foot” by not affording “appropriate deference to the decisions of prison administrators and appropriate recognition to the peculiar and restrictive circumstances of penal confinement.” [82] The Court made clear that the “reasonableness” review first employed in Pell did not change regardless of whether the asserted First Amendment rights were speech or association. [83] Citing Pell , the Court reiterated that inmates retain only those First Amendment rights that are not inconsistent with incarceration, and associational rights are one of the most “obvious” rights curtailed by incarceration. [84] “Equally as obvious” to the Court was the fact that inmates’ prisoner status and additional operational considerations required some restrictions on their ability to associate among each other. [85]

In deciding which restrictions on association were necessary, the Court noted that judges should afford deference to prison officials out of respect for their institutional expertise. [86] Again pointing to Pell , the Court stated that the burden is not on officials to show that the union would thwart the asserted, legitimate goals of the Department in actuality. [87] Rather, in “absence of substantial evidence in the record” that officials’ beliefs were unreasonable, courts must defer to corrections officials’ judgment. [88] The Court therefore rejected the prisoners’ First Amendment associational claim. [89]

As for the inmates’ free speech claim, the Court found that rights to free speech were “barely implicated” by the challenged regulations, as inmates still retained mail rights, just not the right to mail in bulk . [90] Here, where officials enacted reasonable regulations for the legitimate objectives of security and order, and plaintiffs did not show that such concerns were “conclusively” wrong, the Court held that the state’s interests were “sufficiently weighty to prevail” over the inmates’ First Amendment interests, both associational and speech. [91] This last sentiment regarding a “conclusive” showing was especially significant, as the Court indicated that prison administrators did not need to prove that the lack of a regulation would be detrimental to order and security. [92] Instead, their belief that such a threat to security was likely sufficient. [93]

Bell v. Wolfish [94] was the final case to touch on First Amendment free speech challenges to prison regulations prior to Turner . Wolfish involved a First Amendment free speech challenge to the Federal Bureau of Prisons’ so-called “publisher-only” regulation. [95] Under the rule, inmates and pre-trial detainees could only receive hardback books by mail if they were directly ordered from a publisher. [96] Despite the Second Circuit’s assertion that courts should not “second-guess” the choices of administrators “in using reasonable means to insure that its legitimate interests in security are safeguarded,” the court nevertheless struck down the regulation. [97]

Once again, the Supreme Court reversed the circuit court, finding fault with the Second Circuit’s failure to “heed its own admonition” and afford appropriate deference to prison administrators’ judgment. [98] The Court held that the principles of Pell governed the constitutionality of the challenged regulation and applied equally to convicted inmates and pre-trial detainees. [99] Here, as in Pell , the Court found the limited restriction on inmates’ and detainees’ ability to receive hardback books to be a “rational response to an obvious security problem.” [100] The Court was further convinced of the regulation’s reasonableness given its limited duration, neutral operation (without regard to content), and the alternative means of obtaining reading materials available to inmates and detainees, such as the purchase of soft-bound materials. [101] Because the record contained no evidence suggesting the rule was an exaggerated response to security concerns, the Court deferred to the judgment of corrections officials and upheld the rule. [102]

In sum, the Supreme Court carried several themes and a consistent standard of review through these pre­- Turner cases. The most salient principles announced by the Court were that: (1) prisoners, both convicted and detained, have constitutionally-afforded rights, [103] which courts have a duty to protect; [104] (2) a prisoner retains only those First Amendment rights that are not inconsistent with their incarceration; [105] (3) prison officials may additionally restrict the rights of prisoners if the purpose of the restriction is legitimate; [106] and (4) courts should afford prison administrators “wide-ranging” deference in determining the policies and practices necessary to maintain order, discipline, and security. [107] In reviewing First Amendment challenges to prison regulations, the Court looked to whether the regulation reasonably advanced a legitimate penological interest, such as security, and deferred to officials’ judgment in crafting these regulations absent “substantial evidence” that the rules were exaggerated responses to legitimate interests. [108] To determine if the regulations were proportionate responses to the asserted penological interests, the Court considered a number of factors, such as the alternatives available to exercise the impinged right and whether the regulation was content-neutral. [109]

B. Turner ’s “Reasonableness” Standard

It was not until 1987 that the Supreme Court decided on a universal standard of review for constitutional challenges to prison regulations. Turner v. Safley [110] involved a First Amendment challenge to a regulation restricting correspondence between inmates detained in different institutions, [111] as well as a Fourteenth Amendment challenge to a regulation prohibiting inmates from unsanctioned marriages. [112] The Turner Court reviewed its past jurisprudence to synthesize what it believed to be a coherent standard for evaluating these and future claims. [113] The cases from Section I.A of this Note featured prominently in the Court’s analysis, which explained that the post- Martinez case law had not used a standard of heightened scrutiny. [114] The Martinez Court had indeed applied heightened scrutiny, but the Court framed the constitutional rights violation in that case as a violation of non-prisoners’ right to correspondence. Martinez was therefore not relevant in determining what standard of review applied to the inmate-to-inmate correspondence regulation in Turner . [115]

The Court found that the Eighth Circuit below had incorrectly distinguished the Supreme Court’s post- Martinez decisions as either “time, place, or manner” regulations or regulations restricting “presumptively dangerous” inmate activities, believing that the Court had applied heightened scrutiny to those categories of regulations. [116] The Court itself, however, held that the cases had instead applied a “reasonableness” standard, “inquir[ing] whether a prison regulation that burdens fundamental rights is ‘reasonably related’ to legitimate penological objectives, or whether it represents an ‘exaggerated response’ to those concerns.” [117] The Turner Court also markedly expanded the breadth of prison regulation challenges subject to this “reasonableness” review by holding that the same standard applied to all constitutional challenges to prison regulation, rather than the limited subset of constitutional challenges it had considered prior to Turner . [118]

To clear away any remaining confusion stemming from the post- Martinez case law, the Turner Court formally restated the “reasonableness” test as follows: “[W]hen a prison regulation impinges on inmates’ constitutional rights, the regulation is valid if it is reasonably related to legitimate penological interests.” [119] To help guide lower courts in deciding whether a regulation is “reasonably related to legitimate penological interests,” the Court set out four factors or “prongs” based on language and principles from Martinez and its progeny: [120]

  • Whether there is a “valid, rational connection” between the prison regulation and the government interest said to justify the regulation; [121]
  • Whether there are “alternative means” of exercising the right that is limited by the regulation; [122]
  • What impact accommodation of the asserted constitutional right would have on prison administrators, inmates, and prison resources; [123] and
  • Whether there are “ready alternatives” to the chosen regulation. [124]

Having outlined this new standard for evaluating claims, the Court proceeded through each prong to evaluate the regulations at issue in Turner . Although the Court took issue with the “almost complete ban” on inmate marriages, ultimately striking down the regulation, the Court found the correspondence ban to be a reasonable restriction for the purpose of legitimate security concerns. [125] The dissent was critical of the Court’s “highly selective use of factual evidence” in upholding the correspondence ban, [126] noting that the testimony relied upon by the majority was without proof or special knowledge of the conditions at the prison. [127] Such a finding, however, is consistent with pre- Turner case law that required substantial evidence in the record to indicate that challenged regulations were an “exaggerated” response to legitimate penological interests. [128]

C. Post- Turner : The Court’s Subsequent Free Speech Case Law

Only a handful of cases applying the Turner “reasonableness” standard, and even fewer dealing with free speech specifically, have made it up to the Supreme Court in the years since Turner was decided. [129] As predicted by Justice Stevens in his Turner dissent, “plausible security concern[s]” and courts’ deference to prison officials have continuously trumped inmates’ constitutional rights. [130] In fact, the only case in which the Supreme Court struck down a prison regulation of any kind under the Turner test was in Turner itself, almost thirty-five years ago. [131]

There has also been little guidance from the Supreme Court since Turner as to when a regulation burdening free speech is properly considered “arbitrary or irrational” as opposed to reasonable, and, more importantly, what evidence is sufficiently “substantial” to disprove the reasonableness of a regulation. The Court has, for example, upheld regulations that allowed wardens to selectively reject incoming publications purportedly for “order and security,” [132] with no evidence in the record that publications would cause disruptions, nor any evidence that an incoming publication had caused a disciplinary or security problem. [133] The case dealing with this selective censorship regulation, Thornburgh v. Abbott , [134] also made clear that the heightened scrutiny applied in Martinez was cabined solely to prisoners’ outgoing correspondence, and that the content- or viewpoint-specific speech restrictions at issue in the case were subject to the same Turner “reasonableness” standard as the content-neutral restrictions previously examined by the Court. [135]

Most extraordinarily, in the last case in which the Turner test was applied to a free speech challenge by the Supreme Court, the Court held that “deprivation” of prisoners’ access to reading materials and photographs is reasonably related to prisoner rehabilitation and security. [136] In Beard v. Banks , [137] the Court upheld a prison policy whereby officials denied access to newspapers, magazines, and personal photographs for certain classes of prisoners in order to “‘motivate’ better ‘behavior’ . . . by providing them with an incentive to move [to lower security levels].” [138] As Justice Stevens noted in his dissent in Beard , there is no “limiting principle” to this “deprivation theory of rehabilitation.” [139] Any number of constitutional rights could therefore be limited in the name of rehabilitation. [140] The deprivation theory also renders the other Turner factors meaningless. For example, there inherently are no ready alternatives to the policy of deprivation under Turner ’s second factor, because the government interest of rehabilitation is “tied directly to depriving the prisoner of the constitutional right at issue.” [141]

As the most recent case of Beard demonstrates, prisoners’ free speech challenges essentially stand or fall with the first prong of Turner , i.e., whether there is a valid, rational connection between a prison regulation and the purported government interest. [142] The Supreme Court does not appear willing to revisit the standard of review question, having consistently reaffirmed Turner and denied certiorari to cases involving Turner since Beard in 2006. [143] Because the Court has provided little guidance as to what evidence is sufficient to challenge the “valid, rational” connection between a prison regulation and the purported government interest, as well as what volume and kind of evidence amounts to “substantial evidence” that the plaintiff has the burden of producing, circuit courts have had difficulty applying the Turner test uniformly. [144]

II. Turner in the Circuit Courts

This Part reviews the various ways circuit courts apply Turner and the evidence they require a prisoner-plaintiff to provide to disprove a “valid, rational connection” between a regulation and government interest, in absence of meaningful guidance from the Supreme Court. The survey focuses on First Amendment free speech challenges to prison regulations brought in the Third, Fifth, and Ninth Circuits. These particular circuits were chosen to: (1) examine how courts are formulating the plaintiff’s evidentiary burden for free speech challenges under Turner ; and (2) determine if there is a significant difference in the formulation of the evidentiary burden between courts that are thought of as more traditionally “liberal” and “conservative.” [145] These circuits include states with the highest prisoner populations in the country, meaning courts in these jurisdictions have also likely had more opportunities to develop precedent under Turner . [146]

The survey is limited to cases brought between June 28, 2006, the decision date in Beard , and December 15, 2020. [147] Beard was the last major Supreme Court case to address Turner free speech claims and upheld a prison regulation under the expansive “deprivation theory of rehabilitation,” as discussed in Section I.C. [148] Cases decided after Beard would therefore be expected to use a relatively consistent mode of analysis for Turner free speech claims, as no additional case law has come down from the Supreme Court for guidance.

Many of the claims in the reviewed cases involved additional issues with qualified immunity, requirements of the Prison Litigation Reform Act, and the ability to recover damages for First Amendment violations under 42 U.S.C. § 1983, all of which are outside the scope of this Note. [149] The findings below are cabined solely to the courts’ application of Turner , made possible by the fact that the courts often proceed through analysis of inmates’ free speech claims even when these other issues are present and/or serve to invalidate the claim. [150]

A. Third Circuit

The Third Circuit has formulated an evidentiary burden of sorts in evaluating Turner claims. Rather than the four-factor test set out in Turner , the Third Circuit has consolidated the Turner standard into a two-step inquiry: the first step asks whether the first Turner prong is met, i.e., whether there is a valid rational connection, and the second step considers the additional three Turner factors. [151] In line with Turner , the Third Circuit requires that inmates bear the “ultimate burden” of demonstrating that a prison regulation or policy is unconstitutional under Turner . [152] The court has held that prison officials, however, bear the initial burden of demonstrating that a rational connection exists between the regulation/policy and a legitimate penological interest. [153] According to the court, this burden, while slight, must amount to more than a conclusory assertion; but in some instances, where the court finds that the connection is a matter of common sense, no evidence may be required. [154] Whether “common sense” is sufficient to uphold the regulation “will depend on the nature of the right, the nature of the interest asserted, the nature of the prohibition, and the obviousness of its connection to the proffered interest.” [155] Only when neither common sense nor evidence support the connection will the Third Circuit strike down the regulation or find the regulation unconstitutional as-applied. [156]

In short, under Third Circuit precedent, prison officials bear the burden of production for the first step of Turner (which may amount to common sense) whereas inmate-plaintiffs bear the burden of production at the second step and the overall burden of persuasion. [157] For example, there are some cases where the court upholds prison regulations based on an extensive record, complete with reports detailing the exact nature of the security concern a regulation sought to uphold, but other cases where the court found bare assertions that policies were “necessary to maintain prison security and to further rehabilitative goals” or prevented “an adverse impact on the prison library” to be sufficient under Turner . [158]

When reviewing motions to dismiss for claims against regulations alleged to have improperly impinged on inmates’ First Amendment rights, the Third Circuit appears to construe the claims quite liberally. Out of twenty-three identified First Amendment free speech challenges to prison regulations during the fourteen-year period of analysis, only three of these cases came before the court on appeal from motions to dismiss that were adverse to the inmate-plaintiff, one of which was reversed in favor of the plaintiff. [159] The remaining two cases were affirmed, as one case involved a plaintiff who had failed to allege that a prison institution’s practice served no legitimate penological objective, [160] and the other case failed to establish a legal mail violation claim consistent with the court’s interpretation of necessary elements to such a claim. [161] So long as inmate-plaintiffs’ pleadings contained a cognizable First Amendment injury that the plaintiff asserted was not the result of a legitimate penological interest, the Third Circuit generally seemed to allow such cases to advance to discovery. [162]

Despite the court explicitly dividing the evidentiary burden between inmate-plaintiffs and prison administrators, and its liberal construction of inmate-pleadings, inmates bringing claims in the Third Circuit do not seem to fare much better than those in sister circuits with less clear parameters. From 2006 through 2020, the Third Circuit only struck down a single regulation that impinged upon inmates’ First Amendment rights. [163] Notably, the regulation at issue allowed prison officials to read incoming legal mail. [164] The court held that inmate legal mail could only be inspected in the presence of the addressed inmate, [165] a right that had largely been protected by the Supreme Court in the 1974 case of Wolff v. McDonnell and by the Third Circuit in a 1995 case called Bieregu v. Reno . [166] The court declined to move a step beyond Wolff ’s holding, however, later upholding regulations that functionally allowed prison officials to read inmates’ legal mail when the sender had not complied with prison regulations, well beyond the control of inmates whose rights were being infringed. [167]

B. Fifth Circuit

The Fifth Circuit applies an evidentiary burden similar to the formulation of the Third Circuit, where the plaintiff bears the burden of disproving that the regulations are reasonably related to legitimate penological objectives, but prison administrators must do more than show “a formalistic logical connection between [the challenged practice or policy] and a penological objective.” [168] This language does not significantly expand on Supreme Court precedent, but does make clear that prison administrators bear some burden of production when prisoners challenge regulations alleged to be unreasonable. [169] Out of fifty-nine identified First Amendment cases reviewed by the Fifth Circuit since Beard , twenty-two involved a free speech claim. Twelve of the cases were appeals on motions to dismiss, ten on motions for summary judgment, and one from final judgment. In the fourteen-year span of case law examined, the Fifth Circuit did not strike down a single prison regulation that restricted First Amendment free speech rights as unreasonable under Turner .

The Fifth Circuit applies the Turner test very stringently in reviewing motions to dismiss. [170] The vast majority of free speech claims that failed at this stage in a suit were challenges to regulations as-applied. Because these challenges often amounted to disputes about whether or not the application of a regulation to an inmate’s particular circumstances was reasonably related to the government’s asserted interest, the court essentially had to decide between the official’s logic and the inmate’s logic, and deference to officials almost always won the day. [171] For example, in the case of Marino v. Maiorana , [172] an inmate studying cybersecurity was denied receipt of books teaching computer hacking methods under a regulation that prohibited receipt of publications detrimental to security. [173] Marino argued the application of the regulation to his publications violated his First Amendment rights, as he did not intend to use the books for nefarious purposes and had no internet connection. [174] The court found such an argument irrelevant, holding that officials were due deference in their determination that the books posed a security risk inside prison walls, and, in any case, hacking was not limited to networked or desktop computers. [175]

The cases that successfully progressed to discovery during this fourteen-year period and came before the court on appeal from motions for summary judgment primarily fell into one of three categories: (1) challenging a regulation where the state had not provided a sufficiently specific interest in the disputed regulation; [176] (2) challenging a regulation where the state had asserted no interest to uphold the regulation whatsoever; [177] and (3) alleging that the interest asserted by the state was pretextual. [178] It is noteworthy that the cases that progressed to discovery largely dealt with a specific, demonstrable flaw in the state’s asserted interest, rather than merely a challenge to a regulation as-applied. Moreover, even when the court found that prison officials failed to provide an adequate interest for a challenged regulation, officials were allowed to amend their claims with further post hoc rationales to uphold the regulation. [179] As a result, it appears that only truly egregious practices or those explicitly barred by the Supreme Court would be struck down by the Fifth Circuit under their current approach to reviewing Turner free speech challenges.

C. Ninth Circuit

Whereas the Third and Fifth Circuits’ “evidentiary burden” tests appear to be little more than a reformulation of the standard of review for summary judgment, the Ninth Circuit has created an evidentiary standard that is significantly more detailed than Turner or sister circuits. In analyzing Turner claims in the Ninth Circuit, the reviewing court first must look to the pre- or post-trial evidence provided by the inmate-plaintiff, who bears the initial burden of production in the Ninth Circuit. [180] If the evidence is sufficient to “refut[e] a common-sense connection between a legitimate objective and a prison regulation,” then the burden of production shifts to prison officials, who must “present enough counter-evidence to show that the connection is not so ‘remote as to render the policy arbitrary or irrational.’” [181] Alternatively, if the inmate-plaintiff does not present enough evidence to refute a common sense connection between a prison regulation and the objective that the state asserts the policy was designed to further, Turner ’s first prong is satisfied so long as the governmental objective is legitimate and neutral. [182] The test therefore works as a burden-shifting device and creates a more specific threshold of evidence for plaintiffs to meet in order to succeed.

Similar to the Third Circuit, the Ninth Circuit appears lenient in reviewing motions to dismiss and motions for summary judgment, often noting in citations that courts should liberally construe pro se filings, particularly in civil rights cases, and should avoid “applying summary judgment rules strictly” to pro se inmates. [183] The most important development in the Ninth Circuit’s case law during the fourteen-year period of analysis, however, was the court’s creation of clearer benchmarks for inmate-plaintiffs to reach when challenging policies related to legal mail and grievances. The Ninth Circuit, like the Third, requires that inmates be present when prison administrators read legal mail, but has additionally adopted a rule that two or three pieces of mail “opened in an arbitrary or capricious manner” is sufficient to state a First Amendment claim. [184] As a result of the Ninth Circuit’s clear evidentiary threshold, the court was able to overturn an Arizona prison’s policy and practice whereby staff visually scanned the contents of outgoing legal mail, often reading at least some words of every page of outgoing correspondence. [185] The creation of this clear standard also resulted in the court reversing two motions to dismiss where inmate-plaintiffs otherwise would not have been able to state a First Amendment free speech claim regarding the legal mail policies of two different prisons. [186]

The Ninth Circuit has additionally held that disrespectful language in a prisoner’s grievance is itself protected under the First Amendment, in addition to access to the grievance procedure being protected by the First Amendment. [187] As a result, prisoners cannot be cited for disagreeable language in a grievance because such practice could deter prisoners from filing grievances in the first place. [188] This clear rule regarding speech in inmate grievances led the court to overturn summary judgment adverse to inmate-plaintiffs in two cases where prison officials allegedly retaliated against inmates for the speech they used in grievances. [189]

Creating bright line rules such as these for legal mail or grievance claims is significant not only because other circuits appear unwilling to do so, but also because these rules are enormously beneficial for inmates challenging regulations. [190] Turner created a deferential and murky standard, so supplementing case law with clearly established thresholds for succeeding on claims helps curb excessive judicial deference toward prison administrators in the lower courts. These thresholds also make clear to inmates what elements of a claim are necessary to succeed in challenging a given regulation. As a result, the Ninth Circuit was able to safeguard the right to free speech for inmate-plaintiffs more frequently than the Third or Fifth.

D. Commonalities and Splits Among the Circuits

In reviewing inmates’ free speech challenges from 2006 to 2020, several trends among all three circuit courts became apparent and merit additional discussion. These findings are discussed in turn in the subsections below.

1. Commonality: Routine Deference

One striking commonality between the three circuits was the routine handling of as-applied claims once the court had established precedent upholding a particular regulation. In those cases, the reviewing court’s Turner analysis was dramatically shortened, sometimes amounting to a single declaratory sentence. [191] In a paradigm Ninth Circuit case called Roberts v. Apker , [192] the court reasoned that, given “baselines” of precedent upholding regulations, the reviewing court “need only ask whether anything changes” as a result of the inmate-plaintiff’s particular circumstances. [193] The cases reviewed in this fourteen-year analysis suggest the answer is almost always “no.” Similarly, when the Supreme Court had safeguarded the exercise of free speech in a particular fashion, the circuits largely deferred. [194] This practice makes clear just how important Supreme Court precedent is in protecting the free speech rights of inmates and creating a Turner “reasonableness” standard that is not toothless. [195]

The varying formulations of the evidentiary standards under Turner seemed to have little effect on the number or types of prison regulations that courts struck down. Among the Third, Fifth, and Ninth Circuits, despite differing degrees of specificity in the formulations of their evidentiary standards, only two policies/practices were struck down over the course of fourteen years. [196] Moreover, the two policies/practices that were overturned in the Third and Ninth Circuits infringed upon First Amendment free speech rights by interfering with an inmate’s incoming legal mail, which the Supreme Court had already largely safeguarded. [197] The Ninth Circuit’s bright-line evidentiary rules for outgoing inmate legal mail and inmate grievance claims appeared more influential in curbing deference than its comparatively plaintiff-friendly evidentiary standard under Turner . [198]

This review suggests that the more significant issue with Turner claims is the seemingly unbridled deference given to prison officials’ judgment, as courts will generally defer absent glaring issues with prison administrators’ rationale, Supreme Court precedent, or bright-line evidentiary rules, such as those employed by the Ninth Circuit. [199] More plaintiff-friendly formulations of the evidentiary standard, are, however, marginally beneficial in that they can require prison administrators to provide robust factual evidence, which allows reviewing courts to more easily spot issues or deficiencies in the asserted rationale for prison regulations. [200] Such a standard could, at the very least, aid in identifying grossly pretextual regulations or pretextual application of regulations.

2. Circuit Split: Treatment of Incoming Legal Mail

As discussed in Section II.A, the Supreme Court upheld a regulation that allowed prison guards to open all incoming legal mail in the case of Wolff v. McDonnell , [201] but only because the regulation required that inmates were present when the mail was opened. [202] The Court found such a compromise allowed prison officials to address security concerns while still ensuring that prison officials would not read inmates’ legal mail and potentially chill attorney-client communications. [203] The Wolff Court did not, however, locate the exact source of the constitutional right asserted. [204]

Numerous circuit courts have since examined regulations that allowed prison administrators to read inmates’ legal mail in the context of the Sixth Amendment right to counsel and First Amendment right to free speech. [205] At least half of the circuits, including the Third and Ninth, have found First Amendment free speech violations where officials have repeatedly opened legal mail outside the presence of inmates, either pursuant to an improper regulation or in absence of sufficient protections to ensure the violation did not occur. [206] The Ninth Circuit only requires an inmate to demonstrate that two or three pieces of mail were “opened in an arbitrary or capricious manner” in order to find such a violation. [207] The Third Circuit, in contrast, has repeatedly held that a single instance of interference with legal mail is not sufficient to state a First Amendment free speech claim, but has not indicated the minimum number of interferences with mail necessary to establish a “pattern or practice.” [208]

These courts, like the Supreme Court in Wolff , have reasoned that the practice of opening legal mail outside of the presence of the addressee deprives inmates of the expression of confidentiality and chills their protected expression, even if prison administrators maintain that they do not or will not read the contents of the mail. [209] This right to confidentiality in legal mail is noted to be especially important in the prison setting, where inmates’ incarceration and potential distance from attorneys makes face-to-face communication or communication by phone difficult or impracticable. [210] The Fifth Circuit, in contrast, has come to the opposite conclusion, reading Wolff , Turner , and Thornburgh to allow such practices so long as officials credibly claim to have done so in furtherance of a legitimate penological interest. [211]

3. Circuit Split: Treatment of Outgoing Personal Mail

Circuit courts also appear to be analyzing regulations that affect outgoing personal mail under disparate standards. The standard of review set forth in Procunier v. Martinez required that a regulation authorizing mail censorship further “an important or substantial governmental interest unrelated to the suppression of expression,” and that “the limitation of First Amendment freedoms [is] no greater than is necessary or essential to the protection of the particular governmental interest involved.” [212] The Supreme Court cabined this standard to outgoing mail in the case of Thornburgh v. Abbott and clarified that the test is not a “least restrictive means” test. [213] While a number of circuits have held this standard to be controlling law as applied to claims involving outgoing prison mail, including the Third and Ninth, the Fifth Circuit has again bucked the trend. [214] The Fifth Circuit instead has held that Thornburgh can be read to require application of Turner ’s more lax legitimate interest test, though a distinction between incoming and outgoing mail still exists, as “[t]he implications of outgoing correspondence for prison security are of a categorically lesser magnitude than the implications of incoming materials.” [215]

This split in circuit reasoning might not be as significant, however, as Martinez named “security, order, and rehabilitation” as “substantial governmental interests.” [216] As a result, regardless of whether reviewing courts apply Martinez or Turner to a claim challenging a regulation that affects outgoing mail, courts will likely reach the same decision more often than not. For example, the Fifth Circuit found no constitutional violation in the case of Morgan v. Quarterman , [217] where prison officials disciplined an inmate for crude language in outgoing mail to opposing counsel in order to “rehabilitate” the inmate. [218] In Barrett v. Belleque , [219] the Ninth Circuit reversed a district court’s decision on a motion to dismiss where the court had applied Turner rather than Martinez to a similar scenario in which the inmate-plaintiff was disciplined for using crude language in a letter to his grandmother. [220] Per Turner , the district court had originally found that the prison had a legitimate penological interest in preventing the inmate-plaintiff from using such “crude and racist” language. [221] On remand from the Ninth Circuit, the district court reached the exact same conclusion under the Martinez standard. [222] The holding actually went further than Morgan , as the Fifth Circuit had found it relevant that the censored mail was going to opposing counsel in Morgan , rather than a personal correspondent. [223]

III. Balancing Deference and Constitutional Protections

As the review in Part II demonstrated, the current formulations of Turner ’s evidentiary standard do little to combat the routine deference courts afford prison administrators, even in their most plaintiff-friendly formulations. [224] If the Supreme Court were to intervene and mandate a unitary evidentiary standard, such a reform would therefore be unlikely to result in more considered evaluations of prisoners’ First Amendment free speech claims. The following classes of reforms, small- and large-scale, seek to instead shore up the evidentiary burden under Turner and/or create a different standard of review for prisoners’ First Amendment free speech challenges. The reforms classified as “small-scale” are those that can be accomplished unilaterally by the circuit courts, whereas “large-scale” reforms are those that require the intervention of either the Supreme Court or Congress.

A. Small-Scale Reforms

Because the Supreme Court has not granted certiorari on a case involving Turner since 2006, it seems unlikely reform will come from the nation’s highest court. As discussed in Part II, however, circuit courts have been dealing with thorny questions of Turner ’s application for years and have created innovative evidentiary requirements that could be adopted broadly to the benefit of inmate-plaintiffs. Below are a few noteworthy examples of such innovations.

1. Adoption of Bright-Line Evidentiary Rules for Certain Turner Claims

To aid inmates in bringing viable claims and provide clear guidance to lower courts, circuit courts could seek to adopt more bright-line evidentiary rules in reviewing Turner claims. [225] The Ninth Circuit’s precedents establishing the specific number of legal mail violations necessary to bring a First or Sixth Amendment claim, as well as the complete barring of inmate censorship in grievances, are two such examples. [226] The Ninth Circuit actually modeled the standard for First Amendment free speech claims regarding legal mail after the Sixth Circuit, demonstrating willingness on the part of circuits outside this survey to create such bright-line evidentiary rules. [227]

As with any examination of the benefits of rules versus standards, offering more bright-line rules in the context of Turner claims provides the dual benefit of fewer meritless claims coming before circuit courts, allowing them more time and resources to review claims with merit, and more straightforward review in the lower courts, meaning judges would theoretically resort to deference less frequently. [228] Turner is a rather open-ended, subjective standard with deference to administrators built into review. Supplementing this deferential standard with bright-line rules that help protect the constitutional rights of inmates works to balance these competing concerns of courts. As demonstrated in Part II, these clear evidentiary rules appeared more significant in safeguarding the rights of inmate-plaintiffs than courts’ overall evidentiary standards, making them an important and easily implemented reform. [229]

2. Barring of Post Hoc Reasoning

One of the practices most detrimental to successful as-applied prison regulation challenges is the use of post hoc rationales by prison officials. As discussed in the review of Fifth Circuit precedent, some of the only challenges that were able to progress to discovery were those that pointed to serious deficiencies in the asserted interest prison officials sought to advance by applying the regulation to the inmate-plaintiff. [230] In some cases, officials completely lacked a rationale or provided only conclusory assertions as to why the regulation was necessary. [231] Similarly, in other circuits, prison officials would assert facially neutral reasons for applying regulations to prisoners, which were not sufficient to overcome the inmate-plaintiffs’ allegations that the reasons were pretextual. [232] These small victories were often insignificant, however, as prison officials are able to amend the record with post hoc rationales as to why application of the regulation was constitutional. [233] Allowing shifting explanations for application of regulations makes it exceedingly difficult for an inmate-plaintiff to prove a constitutional violation, as prison officials can continue testing out rationales until either the court defers to their “judgment,” or inmate-plaintiffs, who are often proceeding pro se, run out of time or money to litigate their claim. [234]

In order to combat this practice, circuit courts could build a presumption of unconstitutionality into their evidentiary standards when prison officials assert a different rationale for applying a regulation to the inmate-plaintiff during litigation than was recorded at the time the regulation was applied. For example, when publications are rejected pursuant to prison regulations for security or when inmates are cited for violating regulations, prison officials are often required to indicate a reason for the rejection or citation. If, over the course of litigation for such violations, prison officials advance different reasoning for rejecting a book or issuing a citation than what the forms indicate, courts could presume such rationale is pretextual unless officials can demonstrate a valid reason for the shift.

Prior to Turner , the Fifth Circuit actually appeared to implicitly adopt such a presumption as demonstrated by the 1978 case of Guajardo v. Estelle . [235] In Guajardo , the court held that prior to rejection of a publication, prison administrators must review the publication and “make a specific, factual determination that the publication is detrimental to prisoner rehabilitation because it would encourage deviate (sic), criminal sexual behavior.” [236] Although this decision was grounded on the authority of Martinez and since abandoned, such a requirement is not inherently inconsistent with Turner ’s “reasonableness” review. [237] The lack of a specific, factual determination serves to undermine the “valid, rational” connection between the regulation and asserted interest and is consistent with the burden of production for this first prong of Turner being placed on the state in surveyed circuits. [238]

B. Large-Scale Reforms

As noted, the Supreme Court has not revisited Turner since the 2006 case of Beard v. Banks and appears unwilling to do so. This dearth of case law may be due to reluctance on the part of the Court to disturb what they consider to be settled law, but it might also be due to the difficulty in litigating a Turner free speech case and pursuing that claim all the way to the Supreme Court. [239] The circuit splits discussed in this Note present an opportunity for the Court to reopen Turner by clarifying past precedent and avoiding these difficulties on the part of either the Court or litigants. Moreover, the routine deference afforded prison officials absent Supreme Court precedent, as discussed in Section II.D, highlights the need for additional case law from the Court. [240]

Similarly, although major criminal justice reform out of Congress has been stunted and infrequent, the current political climate could allow for progressive policy initiatives. [241] Despite the possibility of congressional gridlock outlasting political will for more substantial legislation, reforms are worth discussing in the event opportunities arise for incremental steps towards change. [242]

1. Resolution of Circuit Splits

As discussed in Section II.D, there were two splits in circuit reasoning that became apparent over the course of this research: (1) treatment of prisoners’ incoming legal mail; and (2) treatment of prisoners’ outgoing personal mail. [243] Starting with the first circuit split, it would be beneficial for the Supreme Court to revisit the application of Turner to regulations that burden prisoners’ incoming legal mail. The Court recognized back in 1974 the importance of safeguarding legal correspondence for inmates, as communication with the outside world is significantly constrained in jails and prisons. [244] Although at least half of the circuit courts have safeguarded legal correspondence by requiring inmates be present when officials inspect incoming legal mail for contraband, the Fifth Circuit refused to do so in 1993 and has consistently affirmed that decision. [245] As the basis for its decision, the Fifth Circuit cited the line in Wolff that noted “by acceding to a rule whereby the inmate is present when mail from attorneys is inspected, [prison officials] have done all, and perhaps even more , than the Constitution requires.” [246] Additionally, the court read Wolff as constrained by Turner and Thornburgh . [247] As lower courts eschew deference most readily under Turner when Supreme Court precedent establishes a right of prisoners, resolution of the split against the Fifth Circuit’s rationale would better protect inmates against potential chilling of speech and confidential legal communications by safeguarding the inspection of inmates’ legal mail. [248]

The benefits of resolving the circuit split regarding the application of Martinez ’s heightened scrutiny standard to inmates’ First Amendment outgoing mail claims post- Thornburgh are less obvious. A comparison between similar cases in the Ninth and Fifth circuits in Section II.D demonstrated that the use of the Martinez standard versus the Turner standard to examine challenges to prison regulations might have little effect on the outcome. [249] Granting certiorari on this circuit split could, however, provide the Court with an opportunity to explain when deference is appropriate in the context of challenges to regulation on outgoing mail. Review would be especially beneficial if the case involved a particularly egregious regulation on outgoing mail, giving the Court another opportunity to strike down a prison regulation and demonstrate that “deference does not mean the abandonment of review.” [250]

Although the Supreme Court is generally unwilling to grant certiorari in cases turning solely on an analysis of the particular facts involved, the two circuit splits discussed in this Note are better categorized as conflicts regarding matters of constitutional law. [251] Regardless of how the facts of the cases are construed, the circuits that have taken minority positions in each split have established legal principles under Turner and Wolff that are seemingly in conflict with Supreme Court precedent. [252] These types of conflicts fall squarely within the character of reasons listed by the Supreme Court’s rule for granting certiorari and therefore are well-suited for Court review. [253]

2. Creating a Statutory Cause of Action for Prisoners’ Free Speech Claims

The Supreme Court in Turner believed heightened scrutiny would undermine the judgment of prison officials, who are in a better position than the judiciary to determine prison administrative needs, such as the oft-cited concerns of security, order, and rehabilitation. [254] As a result, the Court set the standard of review as “reasonableness” review for all constitutional challenges brought against prison regulations. [255] The passing of the Religious Land Use and Institutionalized Persons Act (“RLUIPA”) [256] of 2001 and its subsequent application to prison regulation challenges, however, makes clear that such substantial deference to prison administrators is not necessary to maintain orderly and secure prisons or to accommodate the expertise and judgment of prison officials. [257]

RLUIPA prohibits the government from imposing any “substantial burden” (e.g. a prison regulation) on the religious exercise of an institutionalized person unless the government demonstrates that the imposition of the burden: (1) is in furtherance of a compelling government interest; and (2) is the least restrictive means to further that compelling interest. [258] The act therefore creates a statutory cause of action that applies strict scrutiny review to First Amendment free exercise challenges in the prison environment. [259] This cause of action supplements the constitutional cause of action for First Amendment free exercise challenges, which only requires Turner “reasonableness” review. [260] Importantly, there is little evidence that RLUIPA has negatively impacted prison security, and the federal government has recognized that the use of strict scrutiny review has not compromised prison security or public safety. [261] The Supreme Court has also developed jurisprudence under RLUIPA that reasonably accommodates the expertise of prison officials without compromising the constitutional rights of inmates. [262] The creation of RLUIPA has, however, resulted in paradoxical prison environments where religious publications and exercise of religion are allowed despite regulations severely limiting similar secular practices, all in the name of “security” and “rehabilitation.” [263]

The passing of RLUIPA suggests that Congress considered Turner ’s “reasonableness” review to be inadequate to protect fundamental First Amendment free exercise rights. [264] As First Amendment free speech is a similarly fundamental constitutional right, and RLUIPA has proven that strict scrutiny for constitutional claims in the prison setting will not necessarily undermine security or administrative expertise, a similar law requiring strict scrutiny for free speech is warranted. [265] Rather than the other piecemeal protections described above, providing a statutory cause of action with heightened scrutiny for these claims would be the most effective method of curbing judicial deference and safeguarding First Amendment free speech.

Under the current Turner deference regime, the vast majority of prisoners’ First Amendment free speech claims fail, preventing fathers from writing letters to their children, inmates with muscular dystrophy from being accommodated with typewriters, and whole categories of prisoners from accessing books and magazines in the name of “security,” “order,” and “rehabilitation.” [266] With more than 1.4 million Americans incarcerated, [267] widescale censorship and denial of access to information should not be reviewed under a standard where any “plausible security concern” can trump the fundamental First Amendment rights of inmates and detainees. [268] Justice Stevens warned that such an outcome was likely in Turner itself, but the Supreme Court has failed to provide meaningful guidance as to when deference to officials is appropriate or how inmates can successfully bring claims under the Turner framework in the roughly 35 years since the decision came down. [269] While the proposals offered in this Note in no way guarantee remedies for or prevention of these types of injuries, they could serve to make it easier for inmates to be heard and more likely to have their claims favorably resolved.

* J.D. Candidate 2022, Columbia Law School; B.A. 2018, University of California, Los Angeles. The author would like to thank Professor Brett Dignam for generously lending her time and expertise, Paul Wright for sharing his wealth of knowledge, and the board and staff of the Columbia Human Rights Law Review for their thoughtful feedback and edits. ↑

  Turner v. Safley, 482 U.S. 78, 84 (1987); see also Wolff v. McDonnell, 418 U.S. 539, 555–56 (1974) (“There is no iron curtain drawn between the Constitution and the prisons of this country.”). ↑

  482 U.S. 78 (1987). ↑

  See, e.g. , Overton v. Bazzetta, 549 U.S. 126, 132 (2003) (explaining that the burden is on the prisoner to disprove the validity of the prison regulation); Shaw v. Murphy, 532 U.S. 223, 232 (2001) (noting that to prevail, inmate-petitioner must surmount the presumption that prison officials acted validly within their “broad discretion” and that this burden of proof is “heavy” (citing Thornburgh v. Abbott, 490 U.S. 401, 413 (1989))). ↑

  See discussion infra Section I.C. ↑

  See, e.g. , Dimitrios Korovilas, Pornless Prisons: An Unreasonable Restriction? , 39 U.C. Davis L. Rev. 1911, 1915 (2006) (discussing the split in reasoning between the Third and D.C. Circuits, which applied different evidentiary burdens in Turner challenges dealing with the Ensign Amendment’s prohibition on sexually explicit material in prisons and jails). ↑

  See discussion infra Part I. ↑

  As most challenges to regulations are as-applied, rather than facial, courts often must choose between the rationale of the prison administrator in rejecting a book, for example, or the rationale of the prisoner as to why the application was unreasonable. Deference to prison administrators almost always leads courts to resolve these claims in favor of the state. See discussion infra Part II; see also Sanford L. Bohrer & Matthew S. Bohrer, Just the Facts, Ma’am—Determining the Constitutional Claims of Inmates to the Sanctity of Their Legal Mail , 63 U. Miami L. Rev. 893, 903 (2009) (arguing, after an analysis of Turner , that decisions in prisoner mail cases often turn on the facts, with varying levels of deference afforded to prison officials depending on those facts); Sharon Dolovich, Prison Litigation Reform Act: Forms of Deference in Prison Law , 24 Fed. Sent’g Rep. 245, 245 (2012) (noting that deference in prisoners’ rights cases before the Supreme Court also functions to frame the facts in a manner sympathetic to prison officials as defendants). ↑

  Religious Land Use and Institutionalized Persons Act of 2000 (“RLUIPA”), 42 U.S.C. § 2000cc-1. The differing standards of review between the statutory cause of action under RLUIPA and the constitutional cause of action subject to Turner have demonstrated the important role a less deferential standard plays in protecting prisoners’ fundamental constitutional rights. There are a number of examples where prisoners have prevailed on their RLUIPA statutory claim while losing on their constitutional free exercise claim under Turner , despite the same facts. See David M. Shapiro, Lenient in Theory, Dumb in Fact: Prison, Speech, and Scrutiny , 84 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 972, 979 (2016) [hereinafter Lenient in Theory ] (citing cases in the Fourth, Eighth, Tenth, and Eleventh Circuits where prisoners have prevailed under RLUIPA, but lost under Turner in the same case); see also infra Section III.B.2 (discussing RLUIPA). ↑

  See discussion infra Part I. For clarity and consistency with court precedent, this Note does not use person-first language. For example, the Supreme Court’s open-ended use of the term “prisoner” in early case law led to subsequent challenges by those in pretrial detention. See discussion infra Section I.A. Because these distinctions in terminology were important, particularly in such early case law, this Note replicates the language used by the courts. Person-first language (that is, “incarcerated person,” not “inmate” or “prisoner”) is the preferred method of referring to persons affected by the criminal legal system and should be used where possible. For a brief discussion of the issue, see TaLisa J. Carter, Person-First Language Is Not Enough , Urb. Inst. (May 28, 2021), https://www.urban.org/urban-wire/person-first-language-not-enough [https://perma.c

c/J4U4-K7ET]. ↑

  See discussion infra Parts I, II. ↑

  Mihir Zaveri, Prison Book Bans Called ‘Arbitrary and Irrational ’, N.Y. Times (Sept. 27, 2019), https://www.nytimes.com/2019/09/27/us/banned-books-week-prisons.html [https://perma.cc/GH2X-M6BF]; PEN America, Literature Locked Up: How Prison Book restriction Policies Constitute the Nation’s Largest Book Ban 3–4 (2019), https://pen.org/wp-content/uploads/2019/09/literature-locked-up-report-9.24.19.pdf [https://perma.cc/X4NT-RGCJ]. ↑

  David L. Hudson Jr., Ex-Con Fights for Prisoner Rights and Battles Censorship , A.B.A. J. (Oct. 1, 2016, 4:50 AM), https://www.abajournal.com/magazine/article/prison_legal_news_wright_profile [https://perma.cc/FX5Z-NTES]. ↑

  For an explanation as to why these particular circuits were chosen, see infra notes 145–­146 and accompanying text. ↑

  The Court’s pre- Turner case law is explored at length to demonstrate the convoluted path to Turner , which has made circuit court application of the Turner standard more difficult to this day. See discussion infra Section II.D (exploring circuit splits regarding pre- Turner case law, which the Court’s subsequent precedent, including Turner itself, has not fully clarified). ↑

  Ruffin v. Commonwealth, 62 Va. 790, 795–96 (Va. 1871). ↑

  See Johnson v. California, 543 U.S. 499, 528 n. 2 (2005) (Thomas, J., dissenting) (explaining the origin of the “hands-off” approach and its duration until the 1960’s (citations omitted)); Shaw v. Murphy, 532 U.S. 223, 228 (2001) (summarizing the history of federal courts’ approach to prisoners’ rights challenges). ↑

  Johnson , 543 U.S. at 528–29. ↑

  See Procunier v. Martinez, 416 U.S. 396, 404 (1974); see also Shaw , 532 U.S. at 228 (summarizing the history of federal courts’ approach to prisoners’ rights challenges). ↑

  See Ronald L. Goldfarb & Linda R. Singer, Redressing Prisoners’ Grievances , 39 Geo. Wash. L. Rev. 175, 181 (1970) (explaining the rationales for the judiciary’s “hands-off” doctrine). ↑

  Id. at 176 (detailing prison riots across the country beginning in the 1950’s); Johnson , 543 U.S. at 528 n. 2 (Thomas, J., dissenting) (citations omitted). ↑

  See, e.g. , Cooper v. Pate, 373 U.S. 546 (1964) (overruling a motion to dismiss granted for failure to state a claim where a prisoner in Illinois state prison had brought a First Amendment free exercise claim against the warden); Lee v. Washington, 390 U.S. 333, 333–34 (1968) (affirming district court ruling that applied the Fourteenth Amendment to prisons and jails, prohibiting racial segregation of prisoners); see also Lauren Salins & Shepard Simpson, Efforts to Fix a Broken System: Brown v. Plata and the Prison Overcrowding Epidemic , 44 Loy. U. Chi. L.J. 1153, 1162 (2013) (“Beginning in the late 1960s . . . courts transitioned to a more hands-on approach with respect to inmates’ rights as the need for prison reform began to outweigh separation of powers concerns.”); Terence P. Thornberry & Jack E. Call , Constitutional Challenges to Prison Overcrowding: The Scientific Evidence of Harmful Effects , 35 Hastings L.J. 313, 313–14 (1983) (describing how the “hands off” approach transitioned to “judicial activism with the 1960s litigation over barbaric conditions in the Arkansas prisons” (footnote omitted)). ↑

 Nat’l Rsch. Council, The Growth of Incarceration in the United States: Exploring Causes and Consequences 34–35 (Jeremy Travis, et al. eds., 2014); see also Giovanna Shay & Johanna Kalb, More Stories of Jurisdiction-Stripping and Executive Power: Interpreting the Prison Litigation Reform Act (PLRA) , 29 Cardozo L. Rev. 291, 299 (2007) (describing how the U.S. incarceration rate began rising in the mid-1970s, and was further accelerated over the following two decades by the War on Drugs and “three-strikes” laws that penalized repeat offenders with heightened sentencing). ↑

  Demetria D. Frank, Prisoner-to-Public Communication , 84 Brook. L. Rev. 115, 123–24 (2018) (describing problems resulting from the increase in prison populations in the U.S.). ↑

  Shay & Kalb, supra note 23, at 298 (noting that the Attica riot in 1971 led civil rights organizations like the American Civil Liberties Union to “aggressively and systemically litigat[e] prison cases,” leading to an initial period of prison reform). ↑

  James B. Jacobs, The Prisoners’ Rights Movement and Its Impacts, 1960-80 , in Crime and Justice: An Annual Review of Research 429, 458 (Norval Morris & Michael Tonry eds.,1980) (citing litigation as the driver of reforms to “organizational structure, increased funding, new administrators, changes in personnel policies, new facilities  .  .  .  improved management procedures, etc.”). ↑

  Giovanna Shay, Ad Law Incarcerated , 14 Berkeley J. Crim. L. 329, 332, 335 (2009); Malcolm M. Feeley & Van Swearingen, The Prison Conditions Cases and the Bureaucratization of American Corrections: Influences, Impacts and Implications , 24 Pace L. Rev. 433, 435–36, 438 (2004) (describing the “double-edged sword” of prison bureaucratization that resulted from litigation). ↑

  Shay, supra note 27, at 335. ↑

  Jacobs, supra note 26, at 458; see also Procunier v. Martinez, 416 U.S. 396, 406 (1974) (noting that failure of the Supreme Court to address the “tension between the traditional policy of judicial restraint” and the need to protect constitutions rights in the prison context had led to inconsistent approaches in the lower courts). ↑

  Martinez , 416 U.S at 405–06. ↑

  Id. at 404–05. ↑

  See discussion infra , Section I.A. ↑

  Reed v. Town of Gilbert, Ariz., 576 U.S. 155, 163 (2015) (“[A] government . . . has no power to restrict expression because of its message, its ideas, its subject matter, or its content.” (quoting Police Dep’t of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U.S. 92, 95 (1972))). ↑

  Reed , 576 U.S. at 163. The Supreme Court has gone as far as striking down a municipal code that regulated publicly posted signs on the basis of content. Id. at 172. ↑

 Ronald D. Rotunda & John E. Nowak, 5 Treatise on Constitutional Law-Substance and Procedure § 20.47(a) (2020). ↑

  Id. ; see also, e.g. , Police Dep’t of Chi. v. Mosley, 408 U.S. 92, 98–99 (1972) (explaining potentially permissible “time, place and manner” regulations in the context of picketing). ↑

  See, e.g. , Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 155 (1973) (“Where certain ‘fundamental rights’ are involved, the Court has held that regulation limiting these rights may be justified only by a ‘compelling state interest. . . .’” (citations omitted)); Kramer v. Union Free Sch. Dist. No. 15, 395 U.S. 621, 627 (1969) (explaining that the franchise is the “foundation of our representative society” and therefore deference usually afforded to the judgment of legislators does not extend to decisions about who may participate in public elections). ↑

  Phila. Newspapers v. Hepps, 475 U.S. 767, 777 (1986) (“In the context of governmental restriction of speech, it has long been established that the government cannot limit speech protected by the First Amendment without bearing the burden of showing that its restriction is justified.” (citing, among other cases, First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U.S. 765, 786 (1978); Speiser v. Randall, 357 U.S. 513 (1958))); see also Kramer , 395 U.S. at 627–28 (explaining that where fundamental rights are involved, the state is not afforded the same presumption of constitutionality that they would receive under rational basis review). ↑

  See discussion infra Section I.A. ↑

        Id. at 89; see also discussion infra Section I.B (detailing Turner ’s “reasonableness” test). ↑

  See, e.g. , Overton v. Bazzetta, 539 U.S. 126, 132 (2003) (explaining that the burden is on the prisoner to disprove the validity of the prison regulation); Shaw v. Murphy, 532 U.S. 223, 232 (2001) (noting that to prevail, inmate-petitioner must surmount the presumption that prison officials acted validly within their “broad discretion” and that this burden of proof is “heavy” (quoting Thornburgh v. Abbott, 490 U.S. 401, 413 (1989))). ↑

  Lenient in Theory , supra note 8 (describing how the Prison Litigation Reform Act and the judicial doctrine of qualified immunity, among other obstacles, have made it difficult for prisoners to litigate claims). ↑

  416 U.S. 396 (1974). ↑

  During the preceding decade, the Supreme Court struck down a number of unconstitutional practices of prisons, but Martinez dealt with the relatively novel issue of prison regulations that burdened the constitutional rights of prisoners. See supra notes 26–31 and accompanying text for the import of this distinction. The Court had indicated its willingness to strike down any such regulation a few years prior in Johnson v. Avery , 393 U.S. 483 (1969), where the Court held that “discipline and administration of state detention facilities are state functions . . . subject to federal authority only where paramount federal constitutional or statutory rights supervene.” Id. at 486 (striking down a regulation that burdened the constitutional and statutory rights of inmates to petition for writs of habeas corpus). ↑

  Martinez , 416 U.S. at 398–99. ↑

  Id. at 399–400. In total, three separate regulations came before the Court which specifically prohibited the content of speech. See Transcript of Oral Argument at 11–12, Procunier v. Martinez, 416 U.S. 396 (1974) (No. 72-1465). ↑

  Martinez v. Procunier, 354 F. Supp. 1092, 1095 (N.D. Cal. 1973), aff’d 416 U.S. 396 (1974); see also Transcript of Oral Argument at 12, Procunier v. Martinez, 416 U.S. 396 (1974) (No. 72-1465) (“Our first position is that . . . social mail is not a constitutional right but is a matter for prison administration.”). ↑

  Martinez , 354 F. Supp. at 1096. ↑

  314 F. Supp. 1014 (S.D.N.Y. 1970). ↑

  Carothers , 314 F. Supp. at 1024; see also Martinez , 354 F. Supp. at 1096 (discussing Carothers standard). ↑

  Martinez , 354 F. Supp. at 1096 (citing Morales v. Schmidt, 340 F. Supp. 544 (W.D. Wis. 1972)); Fortune Society v. McGinnis, 319 F. Supp. 901, 904 (S.D.N.Y. 1970). ↑

   Martinez , 416 U.S. at 408. ↑

  Id. (“In determining the proper standard of review for prison restrictions on inmate correspondence, we have no occasion to consider the extent to which an individual’s right to free speech survives incarceration, for a narrower basis of decision is at hand.”). The Court’s avoidance of prisoners’ rights here is especially striking given that the non-prisoner correspondents were not parties to the suit. See id. at 398; Martinez , 354 F. Supp. at 1093. The Court appears to have unilaterally decided on this framing, as the distinction is not mentioned in the lower court opinion nor the oral argument transcript. See generally Martinez v. Procunier, 354 F. Supp. 1092 (N.D. Cal. 1973), aff’d 416 U.S. 396 (1974); Transcript of Oral Argument, Procunier v. Martinez, 416 U.S. 396 (1974) (No. 72-1465). ↑

  Martinez , 416 U.S. at 408–09. ↑

  Id. at 409. ↑

  Id. at 409–11 (citing Healy v. James, 408 U.S. 169 (1972); Tinker v. Des Moines Indep. Cmty. Sch. Dist., 393 U.S. 503, 506 (1969); United States v. O’Brien, 391 U.S. 367 (1968)). ↑

  The Court ultimately adapted language from the landmark case of United States v . O’Brien , 391 U.S. 367 (1968), in creating its final standard of review. O’Brien announced a four-part standard of review to determine whether a law prohibiting the burning of a draft card impermissibly violated the free speech rights of plaintiff O’Brien, who had burned his card in protest of the Vietnam War. Id. at 369, 377. Martinez consolidated the O’Brien standard to develop a two-criteria test: first, the challenged policy or regulation must “further an important or substantial governmental interest unrelated to the suppression of expression;” second, the restriction of First Amendment freedoms may be “no greater than is necessary or essential” to protect the asserted government interest. Martinez , 416 U.S. at 410–11, 413–14. ↑

  Martinez , 416 U.S. at 415 (“Appellants have failed to show that these broad restrictions on prisoner mail were in any way necessary to the furtherance of a governmental interest unrelated to the suppression of expression.”). ↑

  417 U.S. 817 (1974). ↑

  Id. at 819. ↑

  Hillery v. Procunier, 364 F. Supp. 196, 198–99 (N.D. Cal. 1973). Inmates also could not initiate interviews themselves. Id. at 198. Officials were concerned about inmates becoming “prison celebrities” as a result of press coverage and believed that the 1971 escape attempt at San Quentin, resulting in the death of three staff and two inmates, was the climax of interview policy-related disciplinary problems. Id. at 199. ↑

  Pell , 417 U.S. at 822. Whereas in Martinez , the Court could avoid the weighty question of what First Amendment rights survive incarceration by framing the question as the rights of non-prisoners, the Court did not have such an out in Pell . Supreme Court precedent had firmly established that the First Amendment does not guarantee the press “a constitutional right of special access to information not available to the public generally.” Id. at 833–34 (quoting Branzburg v. Hayes, 408 U.S. 665 (1972)). ↑

  For a discussion of the varying standards of review applied by courts to examine prisoners’ First Amendment challenges in the lead up to Pell , see Martinez v. Procunier, 354 F. Supp. 1092, 1096 (N.D. Cal. 1973). ↑

  Note that the Supreme Court was not as explicit as Carothers in its formulation of a standard of review. The district court in Pell had combined the competing lower court precedents, holding that a compelling state interest must be shown to curtail a prisoner’s First Amendment rights, in addition to a showing that the regulation was “reasonably and necessarily” related to the advancement of that justifiable, compelling government interest. Hillery , 364 F. Supp. at 201–02. The Supreme Court’s language qualifying prisoners’ First Amendment rights made clear that it was rejecting the district court’s implication that First Amendment rights of prisoners are as robust as the general public’s and therefore require the same strict scrutiny review. See Pell , 417 U.S. at 822; see also Hillery , 364 F. Supp. at 201 (“It is a fundamental precept of constitutional law that when a state restricts a First Amendment right, especially when that restriction is imposed prior to publication, it must be able to show a  compelling  interest advanced by that regulation.”). “Compelling interest” language does not appear anywhere in the Court’s decision in Pell . See Pell v. Procunier , 417 U.S. 817 (1974). ↑

  See supra note 66. Note that the dissent in Pell also indicates “reasonable and necessary” is the Court’s adopted standard. Pell , 417 U.S. at 837–38 (Douglas, J., dissenting) (“But the prisoners here do not contend that prison officials are powerless to impose reasonable limitations on visits by the media which are necessary in particularized circumstances to maintain security, discipline, and good order.”). ↑

  Pell , 417 U.S. at 822–23. ↑

  Id. at 823–25 (“In order properly to evaluate the constitutionality of [the challenged regulation], we think that the regulation cannot be considered in isolation . . . .”). The majority did not intend to minimize the “particular qualities inherent in sustained, face-to-face debate, discussion and questioning,” but believed alternative means of communication were relevant when balancing First Amendment rights against legitimate governmental interests. Id. at 823–24. ↑

  Id. at 823–24. Under the district court’s “compelling interest” standard, it had rejected the state’s asserted interests to justify the limitation on press interviews, but noted that other reasonable “time, place, and manner” restrictions on interviews could be imposed, such as limiting the length of interviews. See Hillery , 364 F. Supp. at 202. The Supreme Court, in contrast, likened the challenged regulation itself to a reasonable “time, place, manner” restriction. Pell , 417 U.S. at 826–27. As previously noted, the Court refused to apply strict scrutiny to its analysis, which ordinarily accompanies “time, place, manner” restrictions among the general public, but did discuss alternative means of communication in order to decide the reasonableness of the regulation. Turner v. Safley, 482 U.S. 78, 88 (1987) (explaining that Pell discussed alternative means of communication to determine “the scope of the burden” that the regulation imposed on inmates’ First Amendment rights). ↑

  Pell , 417 U.S. at 828–29. ↑

  Id. at 827–28 . ↑

  Id. This evidentiary standard builds significant deference into the prisoners’ rights case law. As Sharon Dolovich explains, “[A]lthough it is ordinarily the job of the trier of fact to hear witness testimony—including expert testimony—and to weigh the evidence presented . . . in prison cases, unless there is ‘substantial evidence’ to suggest that officials’ response was ‘exaggerated,’ courts are to presume the correctness of defendants’ assertions.” Dolovich, supra note 7, at 247 (citing Jones v. N.C. Prisoners’ Lab. Union, Inc., 433 U.S. 119, 127–28 (1977)). ↑

  Pell , 417 U.S. at 827. The Pell Court appeared to place significant weight on the availability of alternatives, mentioning several times that the regulation at issue restricted only one form of communication, alternative means of communication were available, and they would look more critically at a complete ban on inmate communication. Id. at 823–28. ↑

  433 U.S. 119 (1977). ↑

  Id. at 121. ↑

  Id. at 123. ↑

  Id. at 122. ↑

  The three-judge panel of the North Carolina district court hearing the case chose not to directly address whether prisoners retained the right of association, as both parties agreed that the state-defendants permitted inmates to join the Union. N.C. Prisoners’ Lab. Union, Inc. v. Jones, 409 F. Supp. 937, 940–41 (E.D.N.C. 1976). ↑

   Jones v. N.C. Prisoners’ Lab. Union, Inc., 433 U.S. 119, 125 (1977). ↑

  Id. at 129. ↑

  Id. at 125–26 (citing Pell v. Procunier , 417 U.S. 817, 822 (1974)). ↑

  Id. at 126. ↑

  Id. (discussing Procunier v. Martinez, 416 U.S. 396, 405 (1974)). ↑

  Id. at 127–28. This finding by the Court is particularly noteworthy, as the Court placed the burden of proof on prisoner-plaintiffs bringing claims. Recall that when members of the public bring First Amendment free speech claims, the burden of proof is placed on the state. See supra note 43 and accompanying text. ↑

  Id. at 128 (quoting Pell , 417 U.S. at 827). ↑

  Id. at 133. ↑

  Id. at 130–31. The three-judge panel below read Pell to say “prisoners have a First Amendment right to talk about any subject of interest to them that does not conflict with legitimate penological objectives of the institution,” and given that corrections officials permitted the Union, they could find no justified substantial interest in prohibiting inmates from soliciting additional members to join or providing information about the Union. N.C. Prisoners’ Lab. Union, Inc. v. Jones, 409 F. Supp. 937, 943 (E.D.N.C. 1976). Instead of reasonableness review, the district court also applied Martinez ’s “least restrictive means” test. Id. at 944. ↑

  Jones. , 433 U.S at 132–33. ↑

  Id. (“Responsible prison officials must be permitted to take reasonable steps to forestall such a threat, and they must be permitted to act before the time when they can compile a dossier on the eve of a riot.”). ↑

  441 U.S. 520 (1979). ↑

  Id. at 528. ↑

  Id. at 548–49. The “publisher-only” rule formulated before the district court and Second Circuit was significantly stricter than the amended rule that the Supreme Court considered. Id. The rule considered by the lower courts required that books and magazines of any kind come directly from publishers or book clubs, with no exceptions. Id. After the Second Circuit’s decision affirming the district court’s ruling, the Bureau of Prisons amended the rule to apply solely to hardback books. Id. at 549. ↑

  Although the Second Circuit appeared to restate Pell ’s reasonableness review standard at the outset of its holding for the free speech claim, the heart of its analysis instead cited Martinez , among other cases, for the proposition that “courts have jealously protected the inmate in his exercise of First Amendment prerogatives.” Wolfish v. Levi, 573 F.2d 118, 129 (2d Cir. 1978) (citations omitted). Accordingly, the court found that the First Amendment restriction was inconsistent with previous Supreme Court and circuit court case law. Id. at 130. ↑

  Wolfish , 441 U.S. at 544–45 (noting that despite the Second Circuit stating that courts should not “second-guess” the choices of administrators, when reasonable, to safeguard legitimate interests in security, the court “failed to heed its own admonition”). ↑

  Id. at 545–48 (repeating the established principles that convicted prisoners do not forfeit all constitutional protections, but these rights are subject to restrictions and limitations, such as those necessary to maintain security and order, and that prison administrators should be given deference in determining policies and practices necessary to preserve and maintain security, order, and discipline). Note that the “publisher-only” regulation examined by the Court on appeal differed from that of the lower courts. See supra note 95. ↑

  Wolfish , 441 U.S. at 550–51 (noting that hardback books are “especially serviceable for smuggling contraband” into prisons). ↑

  Id. at 551–52 (pointing out that the rule may only operate for about 60 days and, although the rule may increase costs of obtaining published materials, cost advantages do not implicate free speech values). Note that these alternatives differed from those available under the “publisher-only” rule formulated before the appellate court, but the Court was only considering the amended rule in its analysis. See supra note 95. ↑

  Wolfish , 441 U.S. at 551. ↑

  Id. at 545; Jones v. N.C. Prisoners’ Lab. Union, 433 U.S. 119, 129 (1977); Pell v. Procunier, 417 U.S. 817, 822 (1974). ↑

  See, e.g. , Pell , 417 U.S. at 827 (“Courts cannot, of course, abdicate their constitutional responsibility to delineate and protect fundamental liberties.”); Procunier v. Martinez, 416 U.S. 396, 405–06 (1974) (“When a prison regulation or practice offends a fundamental constitutional guarantee, federal courts will discharge their duty to protect constitutional rights.”). ↑

  See, e.g. , Jones , 433 U.S. at 125 (“The fact of confinement and the needs of the penal institution impose limitations on constitutional rights, including those derived from the First Amendment, which are implicit in incarceration.” (citing Pell , 417 U.S. at 822)). ↑

 See, e.g. , Wolfish , 441 U.S at 547 (“[E]ven when an institutional restriction infringes a specific constitutional guarantee, such as the First Amendment, the practice must be evaluated in the light of the central objective of prison administration, safeguarding institutional security.”); Jones , 433 U.S. at 129 (“In seeking a ‘mutual accommodation between institutional needs and objectives [of prisons] and the provisions of the Constitution that are of general application,’ this Court has repeatedly recognized the need for major restrictions on a prisoner’s rights.” (quoting Wolff v. McDonnell, 418 U.S. 539, 566(1974))); Pell , 417 U.S. at 822, 826 (noting that rights to face-to-face communication in prison must give way to “accepted and legitimate policy objectives” of the carceral system); Procunier , 416 U.S. at 412–13 (“[T]he legitimate governmental interest in the order and security of penal institutions justifies the imposition of certain restraints on inmate correspondence.”). ↑

  See, e.g. , Jones , 433 U.S. at 128 (explaining that courts “should ordinarily defer to [the] expert judgment” of corrections officials); Pell , 417 U.S. at 827 (same). The Court has noted that courts should afford this deference both because of prison administrator expertise and because the operation of correctional facilities is a matter with the discretion of the legislative and executive branches. Procunier , 416 U.S. at 405. ↑

  Note that the same principles and mode of analysis applied to pretrial detainees. Wolfish , 441 U.S. at 545–46. ↑

  The Court was never explicit as to how much these factors weighed in its analysis. See generally discussion supra Section I.A. ↑

  Id. at 81, 93. ↑

  Id. at 81, 96. ↑

  Id. at 89. ↑

  Id. at 87 (“In none of these four ‘prisoners’ rights’ cases did the Court apply a standard of heightened scrutiny . . . .”). Note that the Court seems to have implicitly included challenges brought by pretrial detainees in its new standard by including Wolfish and another pretrial detainee case, Block v. Rutherford , 468 U.S. 576 (1984), in its discussion of “prisoners’ rights” cases. ↑

   Turner v. Safley, 482 U.S. 78, 85–86 (1987). ↑

  Id . at 87–88 (“We disagree with the Court of Appeals that the reasoning in our cases subsequent to  Martinez  can be so narrowly cabined.”); see also, e.g. , id . at 88 (“ Pell  thus simply teaches that it is appropriate to consider the extent of this burden when we are called upon to balance First Amendment rights against legitimate governmental interests.” (citations omitted)). ↑

  Id. at 89–90. The Court had never set out the reasonableness review standard employed in pre- Turner case law as clearly as it is set out in Turner . In fact, the language used by the Court in this quote is pulled from a separate line of case law, i.e., due process challenges to conditions of confinement. See Rutherford , 468 U.S. at 586; Bell v. Wolfish, 441 U.S. 520, 539 (1979). When examining First Amendment challenges to prison regulations, the Court used murkier language and cited to the principles announced in Pell . See supra note 66 and accompanying text (explaining that the Court was not entirely explicit in adopting a standard of review for First Amendment challenges to prison regulations). ↑

        Turner , 482 U.S. at 89. Prior to Turner , the Court had only considered constitutional challenges involving First Amendment and (a limited subset of) Fourteenth Amendment rights. See discussion supra Section I.A; supra note 116. ↑

  Turner , 482 U.S. at 89. ↑

  Id. at 89–92. The factors adopted by the Court reflect the same considerations that Pell and subsequent case law addressed. See discussion supra Section I.A. In this way, the Court appeared to preserve the balancing test approach employed by Pell . ↑

  Turner , 482 U.S. at 89 (quoting Rutherford , 468 U.S. at 586). This government interest must be legitimate and neutral, “without regard to the content of the expression.” Id. at 89–90 (noting that a regulation will not be considered legitimate if the “logical connection between the regulation and the asserted goal is so remote as to render the policy arbitrary or irrational” and that prison regulations restricting First Amendment rights must “operate in a neutral fashion, without regard to the content of the expression” (quoting Pell v. Procunier, 417 U.S. 817, 828 (1974); Wolfish , 441 U.S. at 551)). ↑

  Id. at 90 (Jones v. N.C. Prisoners’ Lab. Union, 433 U.S. 119, 131 (1977); Pell , 417 U.S. at 827). ↑

  Turner , 482 U.S. at 90. This factor looks to whether accommodating the right will have a “ripple effect,” i.e., give rise to other prison administrator concerns or overly drain resources. Id. As an example of a “ripple effect,” the Court cited its decision in Jones , a case in which prison officials were concerned that allowing a prisoners’ union to meet and solicit new members could lead to an aggrieved prisoner bloc, threatening security. Jones , 433 U.S. at 123. ↑

  Turner , 482 U.S. at 90 (citing Rutherford , 468 U.S. at 587). The “existence of obvious, ready alternatives” may suggest that the regulation is an “exaggerated response” to prison concerns. Id. at 90. The Court explicitly noted that this fourth factor is not a “least restrictive alternative” test of the kind advanced in Martinez , but rather evidence to consider in weighing a regulation’s “reasonableness.” Id. at 90–91; see also supra note 59 and accompanying text (describing the “least restrictive means” test of Martinez ). ↑

  Turner , 482 U.S. at 99. In short, the Court held that: (1) the prohibition on correspondence was logically related to legitimate security concerns; (2) correspondence was only banned “with a limited class of other people”; (3) permitting inmate-to-inmate correspondence would come at the cost of liberty and safety for other inmates and guards; and (4) there were no “obvious, easy alternatives” to the correspondence ban. Id. at 92. The majority therefore believed the regulation was constitutionally permissible. Id. at 91–93. Although there was “no doubt” that “legitimate security concerns may require placing reasonable restrictions upon an inmate’s right to marry,” the Court found the marriage regulation in Turner to be an exaggerated response to security concerns with “obvious, easy alternatives.” Id. at 97. ↑

  Id. at 105 (Stevens, J., dissenting) (arguing that the majority did not explicitly disagree with any of the District Court’s findings of fact, but rejected the District Court’s conclusion that the ban on correspondence was “unnecessarily sweeping” and advanced its own reasons in support of its decision, none of which had sufficient basis in the record); see also id. at 113 (Stevens, J., dissenting) (arguing that the Court’s differing views as to security concerns between prison marriages and prison mail were “inexplicable,” for example dismissing expert speculation as to the danger of “love triangles,” but accepting speculation about a potential “gang problem” and use of code in prison mail). ↑

        Id. at 106–07 (Stevens, J., dissenting) (pointing out that the prison superintendent’s testimony offered no proof, merely bald assertions of security risks, and that outside witnesses had only discussed the case with the superintendent and visited the prison for a few hours). ↑

  Id. at 86 (citing Pell v. Procunier, 417 U.S. 817, 827 (1974)). ↑

  Specifically, eight cases have come down from the Court since Turner , half of which dealt with First Amendment rights, but only two of which specifically dealt with free speech claims. See Beard v. Banks, 548 U.S. 521 (2006); Thornburgh v. Abbott, 490 U.S. 401 (1989). ↑

  Turner , 482 U.S. at 100–01 (Stevens, J., dissenting) (“Application of the standard would seem to permit disregard for inmates’ constitutional rights whenever the imagination of the warden produces a plausible security concern and a deferential trial court is able to discern a logical connection between that concern and the challenged regulation.”). ↑

  Lenient in Theory , supra note 8, at 983. Note that the regulation struck down did not involve a First Amendment challenge, but rather a substantive due process challenge. Turner , 482 U.S. at 94–95. ↑

   Thornburgh , 480 U.S. at 404, 419 (holding as facially valid two regulations that allow a warden to reject incoming publications based on considerations of security, order, and discipline of the institution). ↑

  Id. at 430 (Stevens, J., dissenting). ↑

   Id. at 401. ↑

 Id. at 413 (“[W]e acknowledge today that the logic of our analyses in  Martinez  and  Turner  requires that  Martinez  be limited to regulations concerning outgoing correspondence.”); see also id. at 414–17 (interpreting Turner ’s requirement that prison regulations restricting First Amendment rights operate “neutrally” to mean that the purpose of the regulation is to promote security by restricting certain content, rather than seeking to restrict content as the end goal). ↑

  Beard v. Banks, 548 U.S. 521, 525 (2006) (holding that, on the basis of the record before the Court, prison officials have provided adequate legal support for a policy denying newspapers, magazines, and photographs to a particular inmate class). ↑

  Id. at 530–31 (quoting the affidavit of Deputy Prison Superintendent Dickson, who explained the “penological rationales” for the deprivation policy). ↑

  Id. at 546 (Stevens, J., dissenting) (“Any deprivation of something a prisoner desires gives him an incentive to improve his behavior.”). ↑

  Id. (Stevens, J., dissenting) (noting that deprivation theory would provide a “rational basis” for any deprivation of a constitutional right, so long as there exists a “theoretical possibility” that the right can be restored by modifying behavior). ↑

  Id. at 547 (Stevens, J., dissenting). The procedural posture of Beard was admittedly unique in that the prisoners opposing summary judgment before the Supreme Court did not submit any “fact-based or expert-based refutation” alleging the unreasonableness of the regulation. Id. at 534. Without any “substantial evidence” from the prisoners’ refuting the policy as reasonable, the prison officials’ assertion that their deprivation policy was reasonably related to their goal of rehabilitation stood as the only version of facts in the record. Id. at 535. The Court did leave open the possibility of challenges to similar policies surviving summary judgment, particularly if the policy operates as a “de facto permanent ban.” Id. at 536. ↑

  See Melissa Rivero, Melting in the Hands of the Court: M&M’s, Art, and a Prisoner’s Right to the Freedom of Expression , 73 Brook. L. Rev. 811, 832 (2008) (pointing to Beard’s cursory discussion of Turner factors two through four, and the Court’s belief that these factors “add little . . . one way or another, to the first factor’s basic rationale” (quoting Beard v. Banks, 548 U.S. 521, 532 (2006))); see also Beard , 548 U.S. at 532 (noting that in Overton v. Bazzetta , the Court only analyzed the other Turner factors after finding that the regulations at issue met the first Turner factor, but such analysis was unnecessary, as the rational relationship to legitimate interests was enough to sustain the regulations). ↑

  See, e.g. , Hammer v. Ashcroft, 570 F.3d 798 (7th Cir. 2009), cert. denied , 559 U.S. 991 (2010) (declining to review a case challenging communication restrictions on death row inmates in federal prison); Prison Legal News v. Sec’y, Fla. Dep’t of Corr., 890 F.3d 954 (11th Cir. 2018), cert. denied , Prison Legal News v. Jones, 139 S. Ct. 795 (2019) (declining to review a case challenging a Florida Department of Corrections regulation as-applied that banned Prison Legal News based on its advertisements). ↑

  See discussion infra Part II. ↑

  The Ninth Circuit has historically been thought of as the most liberal, whereas the Fifth, located in the Deep South, has traditionally been thought of as conservative. Andreas Broscheid, Comparing Circuits: Are Some U.S. Courts of Appeals More Liberal or Conservative than Others? , 45 L. & Soc’y Rev. 171, 180 (2011). The Third Circuit has been described as both liberal and conservative. Id. This spectrum of ideologies lent itself well to the limited survey of this paper. After speaking with advocates who litigate Turner claims nationally, these three circuits were also ideal case studies due to their varied willingness to overturn prison regulations over time. Anecdotally, the Ninth Circuit is known to be most favorable to prisoners’ claims, the Third Circuit occasionally will overturn regulations, and the Fifth Circuit is known to be more hostile to prisoners’ claims. This spectrum mirrors the ideological reputations of the three circuits. ↑

  Texas and California have the highest prisoner populations by state, with a respective 163,628 inmates and 128,625 inmates at last count. E. Ann Carson, U.S. Dep’t. of Just., Prisoners in 2019, at 4 (2020). Pennsylvania is sixth highest, with 47,239 inmates. Id. ↑

  See Beard v. Banks, 548 U.S. 521 (2006). ↑

  See discussion supra Section I.C. ↑

        For a discussion of the doctrine of qualified immunity and its many deficiencies, see Joanna C. Schwartz, The Case Against Qualified Immunity , 93 Notre Dame L. Rev. 1797 (2018). For a discussion of how qualified immunity, the Prison Litigation Reform Act, Turner , and other situational barriers collectively prevent effective prisoner litigation, see David M. Shapiro & Charles Hogle,  The Horror Chamber: Unqualified Impunity in Prison , 93 Notre Dame L. Rev. 2021 (2018). A Jailhouse Lawyer’s Manual also provides a comprehensive discussion of qualified immunity, prisoner litigation under 42 U.S.C. § 1983, and the Prison Litigation Reform Act. Colum. Hum. Rts. L. Rev., A Jailhouse Lawyer’s Manual, chs. 14, 16, 19 (12th ed. 2020). ↑

  Note that this survey was inherently limited by the cases made available to legal research databases, such as LexisNexis and Westlaw. Between the three circuits, 107 cases were identified as dealing with First Amendment free speech claims under Turner and analyzed for this Part. Many of these cases were not published in an official reporter and are therefore not precedential. Such cases cited in this Note can be readily identified by their citation to the Federal Appendix. ↑

  See, e.g. , Jones v. Brown, 461 F.3d 353, 360 (3d Cir. 2006) (organizing the Turner prongs into two, rather than four, steps). ↑

  Jones , 461 F.3d at 360. Although this reasoning is consistent with Turner and subsequent Supreme Court precedent, the Court has never explicitly noted that prison administration bears the burden of production as to Turner’s first prong. ↑

  Id. at 360–61. ↑

  Id. (citing Wolf v. Ashcroft, 297 F.3d 305, 308–09 (3d Cir. 2002)). ↑

  Jones , 461 F.3d at 361. ↑

  The evidentiary burden for the first step of the court’s Turner analysis therefore functions as a sliding-scale burden of production, which turns on how “obvious” the connection between the regulation and the legitimate penological interest put forward by administrators is. Id. at 360–61 (citing Wolf , 297 F.3d at 308–09). ↑

  Compare Fontroy v. Beard, 559 F.3d 173, 177–78 (3d Cir. 2009) (upholding regulation that allowed prison administrators to open incoming legal mail not deemed “Privileged Correspondence” where record contained two extensive reports detailing how prior legal mail policy was abused), and Solan v. Zickefoose, 530 F. App’x 109, 110 (3d Cir. 2013) (per curiam) (upholding motion to dismiss granted to prison warden where inmate challenged his bar on access to prison email system; warden based her decision on the fact that inmate had extensive prior knowledge with computer systems and documented misuse of prison computer systems), with Brooks v. Bledsoe, 682 F. App’x 164, 168–69 (3d Cir. 2017) (per curiam) (finding that prison met its slight burden to show rational connection between regulation and Ensign Amendment, which barred nude/sexually explicit materials from prison), and Aulisio v. Chiampi, 765 F. App’x 760, 764 (3d Cir. 2019) (per curiam) (summarily agreeing that a policy preventing inmate library workers from working on personal matters while on duty satisfied Turner ’s first step). In Brooks , the district court found that plaintiff had not met his burden as to Turner ’s second step, i.e., Turner prongs two through four. This lack of evidence did not, however, influence the district court judge’s opinion as to the first Turner factor. ↑

  Nixon v. Sec’y Pa. Dep’t of Corr., 501 F. App’x 176 (3d Cir. 2012) (per curiam) (affirming the lower court’s dismissal); Newman v. Beard, 617 F.3d 775 (3d Cir. 2010) (affirming the lower court’s dismissal); Gattis v. Phelps, 344 F. App’x 801 (3d Cir. 2009) (per curiam) (reversing a motion to dismiss for plaintiff’s First Amendment free speech claim, as lower court did not apply Turner to plaintiff’s specific circumstances, namely confinement on death row). It is also noteworthy that the bulk of the period of analysis for this research, 2006–2020, fell after the Supreme Court’s decision in Ashcroft v. Iqbal , 556 U.S. 662 (2009). Iqbal heightened the civil pleading requirement to prohibit claims based on “conclusory statements,” instead requiring plaintiffs to plead particularized facts establishing each element of the claim. Id. at 678–79. Despite the more rigorous pleading requirement, the court appears to have maintained a low bar to inmate-plaintiffs bringing claims. ↑

  Newman , 617 F.3d at 781. ↑

  Nixon , 501 F. App’x at 178. ↑

  There are valid policy reasons for this approach: inmates need access to discovery to make proper claims, meaning a lenient pleading standard makes sense from a due process perspective. Additionally, inmates face resource shortages and are often proceeding pro se. See, e.g. , Smith v. Johnson, 202 F. App’x 547, 549 (3d Cir. 2006) (noting in a case dealing with a prisoner’s First Amendment free exercise claim that the court has “an obligation to liberally construe  pro se  civil rights complaints” (citations omitted)). ↑

  See Jones v. Brown, 461 F.3d 353, 355 (3d Cir. 2006) (holding that the prison had not demonstrated its legal mail policy, which allowed officials to open mail outside inmates’ presence, was reasonably related to asserted interest in safety and security). ↑

  Id. at 355–56. ↑

  Wolff v. McDonnell, 418 U.S. 539, 576–77 (1974); Bieregu v. Reno, 59 F.3d 1445, 1458 (3d Cir. 1995) abrogated on other grounds by  Lewis v. Casey, 518 U.S. 343 (1996). ↑

  Fontroy v. Beard, 559 F.3d 173, 180–81 (3d Cir. 2009) (upholding a prison policy that allowed prison officials to read incoming legal mail unless the sender had used a “Control Number” on the envelope obtained by the prison, despite finding that “some attorneys and all courts have refused the Inmates’ repeated requests” to obtain and use a control number). ↑

  Prison Legal News v. Livingston, 683 F.3d 201, 215 (5th Cir. 2012) (quoting Beard v. Banks, 548 U.S. 521, 535 (2006)). ↑

  In stating this burden, for example, the Fifth Circuit cited directly to Overton v. Bazzetta , 539 U.S. 126 (2003), Beard v. Banks , 548 U.S. 521 (2006), and Turner v. Safley , 482 U.S. 78 (1987) itself. Livingston , 683 F.3d at 215. ↑

  See, e.g. , Samford v. Dretke, 562 F.3d 674, 674 (5th Cir. 2009) (per curiam) (affirming a motion to dismiss where inmate-plaintiff challenged application of a regulation to his circumstances and put forward evidence disputing the reasonableness of the regulation beyond mere assertions). Note that the Fifth Circuit was exacting in reviewing claims even prior to Iqbal ’s heightened pleading requirement, as Samford demonstrates. See supra note 158 and accompanying text. ↑

  The sole exception to this de facto rule seems to be cases where the inmate alleges that the interest asserted by the prison administration was pretextual. See infra note 177 and accompanying text. ↑

  707 F. App’x 812 (5th Cir. 2018) (per curiam). ↑

  Id. at 812. ↑

  Id. at 812–13. ↑

  Id. at 813. ↑

  See, e.g. , Spence v. Nelson, 533 F. App’x 368, 372 (5th Cir. 2013) (per curiam) (reviewing a motion for summary judgment where prison official had rejected packages from Iran due to “security problems,” but did not state why an absolute ban was necessary to address the “non-specific and unattributed security concerns”); Wells v. Vannoy, 546 F. App’x 340, 342 (5th Cir. 2013) (per curiam) (granting motion for summary judgment, as prison officials had pointed to specific information in the rejected publication over the course of litigation that was grounds for security concerns). ↑

  See, e.g. , Keys v. Torres, 737 F. App’x 717, 718 (5th Cir. 2018) (per curiam) (reviewing a motion for summary judgment where plaintiff alleged prison officials had only cited an interest in rejecting one publication, but had subsequently rejected several publications with no asserted interest for doing so); Turner v. Cain, 647 F. App’x 357, 364 (5th Cir. 2016) (per curiam) (overturning a motion for summary judgment and instructing the lower court to bear in mind on remand that the prison official had only provided a “general justification” for his assertion that the restricted speech was unprotected, and did not point to any legitimate penological interest in restricting plaintiff-inmate’s speech). ↑

  See, e.g. , Ayers v. Johnson, 247 F. App’x 534, 535 (5th Cir. 2007) (per curiam) (reviewing a motion for summary judgment where plaintiff had asserted the prison’s denial of his publications for the stated interest of preventing racial conflict was pretextual). ↑

  For example, in Spence v. Nelson , 603 F. App’x 250 (5th Cir. 2015) (per curiam), the Fifth Circuit granted summary judgment in favor of prison officials on a challenge to a regulation where packages from Iran were rejected due to “security problems.” The court had previously denied a motion for summary judgment on the same claim because officials provided insufficient evidence as to the security concerns arising from package delivery from Iran, but, on remand, the defendants submitted additional evidence as to why the policy was constitutional. Id. at 255–56. ↑

  Frost v. Symington, 197 F.3d 348, 357 (9th Cir. 1999) (reconciling perceived differences in the standards of review put forward for Turner in previous cases of Mauro v. Arpaio , 188 F.3d 1054 (9th Cir. 1999) and Walker v. Sumner , 917 F.2d 382 (9th Cir. 1990)). ↑

  Frost , 197 F.3d at 357 (quoting Turner v. Safley, 482 U.S. 78, 89-90 (1987)). ↑

  See, e.g. , Sawyer v. Macdonald, 768 F. App’x 669, 671 (9th Cir. 2019) (“We have ‘held consistently that courts should construe liberally motion papers and pleadings filed by pro se inmates and should avoid applying summary judgment rules strictly.’” (quoting Soto v. Sweetman, 882 F.3d 865, 872 (9th Cir.), cert. denied , 139 S. Ct. 480 (2018))); Blaisdell v. Frappiea, 729 F.3d 1237, 1241 (9th Cir. 2013) (“Courts in this circuit have an obligation to give a liberal construction to the filings of pro se litigants, especially when they are civil rights claims filed by inmates.”). Out of 60 identified free speech challenges to regulations from 2014–2020, the Ninth Circuit reversed 18 judgments (on both motions to dismiss and motions for summary judgment) that were adverse to inmate-plaintiffs. ↑

  Hayes v. Idaho Corr. Ctr., 849 F.3d 1204, 1211 (9th Cir. 2017). If the legal mail examined pertains to a criminal matter, inmates can also bring a claim under the Sixth Amendment. The Ninth Circuit is even more protective of Sixth Amendment claims, maintaining that a single incident of a prison official reading inmate legal mail is sufficient to state a claim under the Sixth Amendment. See Nordstrom v. Ryan 865 F.3d 1265, 1268 (9th Cir. 2017); Nordstrom v. Ryan, 762 F.3d 903, 911 (9th Cir. 2014). ↑

  Nordstrom , 856 F.3d at 1274 (granting inmate-plaintiff’s motion for injunctive relief against the Arizona Department of Correction’s mail policy and practice of inspecting inmates’ outgoing legal mail, finding that the policy and practice violated inmates’ First Amendment right to free speech and Sixth Amendment right to counsel). ↑

   Hayes , 849 F.3d at 1206; Mangiaracina v. Penzone, 849 F.3d 1191, 1203 (9th Cir. 2017). Both Hayes and Mangiaracina were later decided against the inmate-plaintiffs on the merits of their First Amendment claims due to only two isolated instances of prison officials opening legal mail, with no evidence of “reckless” or “intentional” misconduct on the part of these officials. Mangiaracina , 849 F.3d at 1198; Hayes v. ICC-CCA, 2018 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 152165, at *7 (D. Idaho 2018). ↑

  Richey v. Dahne, 624 F. App’x 525, 525 (9th Cir. 2015) (“We have previously held that disrespectful language in a prisoner’s grievance is itself protected activity under the First Amendment.” (citing Brodheim v. Cry, 584 F.3d 1262, 1271 (9th Cir. 2009))). ↑

  Richey v. Dahne, 733 F. App’x 881, 883 (9th Cir. 2018) (“In Brodheim  we held squarely that no legitimate penological interest is served by prison rules prohibiting disrespectful language in grievances.” (citing Brodheim , 584 F.3d at 1273)). ↑

  See Richey , 624 F. App’x at 526; Brodheim , 584 F.3d at 1262. Unfortunately, qualified immunity barred the inmate-plaintiff in Richey from recovering under First Amendment free speech grounds on remand, despite the court finding that the actions taken by defendant-prison official “[was] the sort of content-based discrimination that runs contrary to First Amendment Protections.” Richey , 733 F. App’x at 883, cert denied , Dahne v. Richey, 139 S. Ct. 1531 (2019). The disposition of Brodheim is unknown, as the last entry in any legal database is the granting of inmate-plaintiff’s motion to submit a fourth amended and supplemental complaint. Brodheim v. Cry, 2010 WL 3943558, at *1 (E.D. Cal. 2010). ↑

 Bright line rules can also prove advantageous to courts as they allow reviewing courts to dispose of meritless claims more efficiently. See discussion infra Section III.A.1. ↑

  In the Third Circuit, see, e.g., Robinson v. Pa. Dep’t of Corr., 327 F. App’x 321, 323 (3d Cir. 2009) (per curiam) (“Because we have already considered all of the arguments raised by Appellants in their brief and response to our order, we will summarily affirm the judgment of the District Court for all of the reasons given in Fontroy v. Beard .” (citing Fontroy v. Beard, 559 F.3d 173 (3d Cir. 2009))); Harper v. Beard, 326 F. App’x 630, 633 (3d Cir. 2009) (per curiam) (“Having received responses from all of the parties to this appeal, we conclude that this appeal presents no ‘substantial question,’ and will summarily affirm the judgment of the District Court for all of the reasons given in its thorough opinions and in our opinion in Fontroy v. Beard .” (citing Fontroy v. Beard, 559 F.3d 173 (3d Cir. 2009))). In the Fifth Circuit, see, e.g., Lee v. Smith, 552 F. App’x 331, 331 (5th Cir. 2014) (per curiam) (“[Plaintiff] has failed to show that the placement of his children on the negative mailing list ran afoul of his constitutional rights.” (citing Samford v. Dretke, 562 F.3d 674 (5th Cir. 2009) (per curiam))). In the Ninth Circuit, see, e.g., Roberts v. Apker, 570 F. App’x 646, 648 (9th Cir. 2014) (“Given the baselines of Bahrampour and Mauro , we need only ask whether anything changes in the context of a convicted sex offender . . . when the application of the Turner factors moves from content that is ‘sexually explicit’ . . . or contains full-frontal ‘nudity’ to content that is only ‘sexually suggestive’ . . . .”). ↑

  Roberts , 570 Fed App’x. at 646. ↑

  Id. at 648. ↑

  As Turner free speech claims have not been widely litigated, the sole example available was incoming legal mail, which the Supreme Court had safeguarded in Wolff v. McDonnell , 418 U.S. 539 (1975). See generally Jones v. Brown, 461 F.3d 353, 355 (3d Cir. 2006) (holding that opening legal mail outside the presence of prisoners impinged upon freedom of speech); Hayes v. Idaho Corr. Ctr., 849 F.3d 1204, 1210 (9th Cir. 2017) (same). The Fifth Circuit was an apparent anomaly. See discussion infra Section II.D.1. ↑

  Although the Supreme Court asserted that Turner ’s reasonableness standard is not “toothless” in the case of Thornburgh v. Abbott , 490 U.S. 401, 414 (1989), this survey, and the Court’s own precedent, would suggest otherwise. ↑

  Jones , 461 F.3d at 353; Hayes , 849 F.3d at 1204. ↑

  As discussed, in addition to the policy and practice struck down by the court in Hayes , the Court also overturned motions to dismiss and motions for summary judgment on claims dealing with outgoing legal mail and speech in grievances. Hayes , 849 F.3d at 1204; Mangiaracina v. Penzone, 849 F.3d 1191, 1193 (9th Cir. 2017); Richey v. Dahne, 624 F. App’x 525, 525 (9th Cir. 2015); Brodheim v. Cry, 584 F.3d 1262, 1264 (9th Cir. 2009). ↑

  For a comprehensive discussion of the forms of deference found in prison law, and how all three forms are present in the Supreme Court’s Turner jurisprudence, see generally Dolovich, supra note 7. ↑

  See, e.g. , Shepard v. Quillen, 840 F.3d 686, 692 (9th Cir. 2016) (rejecting a “general justification” that placing an inmate in administrative segregation was the result of a neutral process and requiring more evidence where the inmate-plaintiff alleged the segregation was retaliatory). ↑

  418 U.S. 539 (1974). ↑

  Id. at 576–77. ↑

  Id. at 576 (“We need not decide, however, which, if any, of the asserted rights are operative here, for the question is whether, assuming some constitutional right is implicated, it is infringed by the procedure now found acceptable by the State.”). ↑

  The Second, Third, Sixth, Ninth, Tenth, and Eleventh Circuits “have recognized that the opening of legal mail outside of a prisoner’s presence implicates First Amendment rights.” Hayes v. Idaho Corr. Ctr., 849 F.3d 1204, 1210 (9th Cir. 2017). ↑

  Id. The Sixth and Ninth Circuits, for example, have held that “[t]wo or three pieces of mail opened in an arbitrary or capricious way suffice to state a claim” under the First Amendment. Id. at 1211; Merriweather v. Zamora, 569 F.3d 307, 317 (6th Cir. 2009) (same). ↑

  Hayes , 849 F.3d at 1211. ↑

  See, e.g. , Schreane v. Holt, 482 Fed. App’x 674, 677 (3d Cir. 2012) (per curiam) (“[A] single instance of opening special mail outside an inmate’s presence does not rise to the level of a constitutional deprivation.”); Bieregu v. Reno, 59 F.3d 1445, 1452 (3d Cir. 1995) (“We decline to hold that a single instance of damaged mail rises to the level of constitutionally impermissible censorship.”), abrogated on other grounds by  Lewis v. Casey, 518 U.S. 343 (1996). ↑

  See, e.g. , Hayes , 849 F.3d at 1209–10 (agreeing with other circuits that the opening of legal mail could dissuade an inmate from further communicating about privileged matters); Jones v. Brown, 461 F.3d 353, 359 (3d Cir. 2006) (holding that the opening of legal mail outside of the presence of the addressee inmate “interferes with protected communications,” and “strips those protected communications of their confidentiality”). ↑

  See, e.g. , Hayes , 849 F.3d at 1210–11 (noting that prisoners’ avenues of confidential communication with attorneys is limited, making confidential legal mail that much more important); Al-Amin v. Smith, 511 F.3d 1317, 1333–34 (11th Cir. 2008) (noting that use of mail for prisoners may often be a more important speech right “than the use of their tongues,” due to their frequent distance from attorneys). ↑

  Brewer v. Wilkinson, 3 F.3d 816, 822–25 (5th Cir. 1993). ↑

  Procunier v. Martinez, 416 U.S. 396, 413–14 (1974). ↑

       Thornburgh v. Abbott, 490 U.S. 401, 411 (1989) (“We do not believe that Martinez  should, or need, be read as subjecting the decisions of prison officials to a strict ‘least restrictive means’ test.”). ↑

  The Third, Eighth, and Ninth hold Martinez to be controlling law as applied to outgoing prisoner mail claims. Barrett v. Belleque, 544 F.3d 1060, 1062 (9th Cir. 2008) (per curiam). ↑

  Brewer , 3 F.3d at 825. ↑

  Martinez , 416 U.S. at 413–14. ↑

  570 F.3d 663 (5th Cir. 2009). ↑

  Id. at 665. ↑

  544 F.3d 1060 (9th Cir. 2008) (per curiam). ↑

  Id. at 1061. ↑

  Barrett v. Belleque, 2010 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 141768, at *20 (D. Or. 2010) (“[T]he record before the court will support only the conclusion that the censorship and discipline at issue furthered important governmental interests in prison security, order, and prisoner rehabilitation, and that the limitations imposed upon plaintiff’s First Amendment rights were no more onerous than were needed to protect those interests.”). ↑

  Morgan v. Quarterman, 570 F.3d 633, 667 (5th Cir. 2009) (distinguishing a previous Fifth Circuit case where the court had found refusal to mail a personal letter with crude language to violate the First Amendment, as the letter at issue in the case before the court was intended for opposing counsel in connection with pending litigation). ↑

  See discussion supra Section II.D. ↑

  Increasing the number of viable claims brought under Turner also allows courts to further develop the law, which creates additional guidance for lower courts via case law. ↑

  Hayes v. Idaho Corr. Ctr., 849 F.3d 1204, 1211 (9th Cir. 2017) (finding two or three pieces of mail “opened in an arbitrary or capricious way” sufficient to state a First Amendment claim); Richey v. Dahne, 733 F. App’x 881, 883 (9th Cir. 2018) (“[R]ules prohibiting disrespectful language do not serve a legitimate penological interest in the special context of prison grievances . . . .”); Nordstrom v. Ryan, 762 F.3d 903, 910–11 (9th Cir. 2014) (holding that a single instance of a guard reading a prisoner’s mail was sufficient to establish a violation of the Sixth Amendment right to counsel). ↑

  Merriweather v. Zamora, 569 F.3d 307, 318 (6th Cir. 2009). ↑

  For a discussion of the classic rules versus standards debate, see Michael Coenen, Rules Against Rulification , 124 Yale L.J. 644, 646 (2014). ↑

 See discussion supra Part II. Although courts are generally reluctant to articulate bright-line rules due to concerns about violating the separation of powers by adopting “judge-made law” and questions of institutional competence, the Ninth Circuit only announced the cited evidentiary rules in order to decide the cases before it. See, e.g. , Caleb Nelson, The Legitimacy of (Some) Federal Common Law , 101 Va. L. Rev. 1 (2015) (discussing modern criticisms of so-called “judge-made” law). So long as sister circuits adopt these or other bright-line evidentiary rules in the context of a case with applicable facts, there can be no allegations of constitutional impropriety. For a thorough discussion of the bright-line rule quandary, see Colon v. Howard, 215 F.3d 227 (2d Cir. 2000). ↑

  See, e.g. , Keys v. Torres, 737 F. App’x 717, 718 (5th Cir. 2018) (per curiam) (reviewing a motion for summary judgment where plaintiff alleged prison officials had only cited an interest in rejecting one publication, but had subsequently rejected several publications with no asserted interest for doing so); Turner v. Cain, 647 Fed. App’x 357, 364 (5th Cir. 2016) (per curiam) (overturning a motion for summary judgment and instructing the lower court to bear in mind on remand that the prison official had only provided a “general justification” for his assertion that the restricted speech was unprotected, and did not point to any legitimate penological interest in restricting plaintiff-inmate’s speech). ↑

   For example, in the case of Spence v. Nelson , 603 F. App’x 250, 251 (5th Cir. 2015) (per curiam), the court granted summary judgment for prison officials on a challenge to a regulation where packages from Iran were rejected due to “security problems.” The court had initially denied a motion for summary judgment on the same claim, as officials provided insufficient evidence as to the security concerns arising from package delivery from Iran. On remand, however, the court allowed defendants to submit additional evidence as to why the policy was constitutional, leading to the subsequent grant of summary judgment. ↑

  For a detailed example of shifting prison rationales in practice, see Lenient in Theory , supra note 8, at 1005–12. ↑

  580 F.2d 748 (5th Cir. 1978). ↑

  Id. at 762. ↑

  Id. at 753–54. ↑

  In fact, courts do seem to scrutinize post hoc rationales more heavily in the context of free exercise claims. Koger v. Mohr, 964 F.3d 532, 542 (6th Cir. 2020) (denying a motion for summary judgment on an RLUIPA claim where prison officials had not provided a reason for denying an inmate’s religious diet requests until litigation began); Davis v. Davis, 826 F.3d 258, 265 (5th Cir. 2016) (noting that post hoc rationales by prison officials are not entitled to deference). This heightened scrutiny, however, is often tied to congressional intent to bar flippant restrictions on religious freedom via the RLUIPA. See, e.g. , Rich v. Fla. Dep’t of Corr., 716 F.3d 525, 533 (11th Cir. 2013) (“[P]ost-hoc rationales will not suffice to meet [RLUIPA’s] requirements.”). For a fuller explanation of RLUIPA and its history, see discussion infra Section III.B.2. ↑

  See, e.g. , supra note 148 (explaining the difficulties associated with litigating prisoner claims, both procedural and situational). ↑

  After a summer of protests over racial injustice and police brutality, Congress did signal some political will for criminal justice reform, such as proposed legislation to end qualified immunity. See, e.g. , Leah Millis, US Saw Summer of Black Lives Matter Protests Demanding Change , Reuters (Dec. 10, 2020), https://widerimage.reuters.com/story/us-saw-summer-of-black-lives-matter-protests-demanding-change [https://perma.cc/XD6U-SJBB]; Colleen Long, Kat Stafford & R.J. Rico, Summer of Protest: Chance for Change, But Obstacles Exposed , AP News (Sept. 6, 2020), https://apnews.com/article/9035ecdfc58d5dba755185666ac0ed6d [https://per ma.cc/C6WC-3VVQ]; Ending Qualified Immunity Act Bill, H.R. 7085, 116th Cong. (2020). ↑

  The slim single-party majorities in both chambers of the 117th Congress and increasing political polarization in America could hinder significant bipartisan criminal justice reform. See John Wagner et al., Democrats Win Control of U.S. Senate as Ossoff Defeats Perdue , Wash. Post (Jan. 6, 2021), https://www.washingtonpost.com/politics/ 2021/01/06/georgia-senate-election-results-live-updates/ [https://perma.cc/V57P-KAMR]; Claudia Deane & John Gramlich, 2020 Election Reveals Two Broad Voting Coalitions Fundamentally at Odds , Pew Rsch. Ctr. (Nov. 6, 2020), https://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2020/11/06/2020-election-reveals-two-broad-voting-coalitions-fundamentally-at-odds/ [https://perma.cc/CF6P-3VQ9]. ↑

  See generally Wolff v. McDonnell, 418 U.S. 539 (1974). ↑

  The Second, Third, Sixth, Ninth, Tenth, and Eleventh Circuits “have recognized that the opening of legal mail outside of a prisoner’s presence implicates First Amendment rights.” Hayes v. Idaho Corr. Ctr., 849 F.3d 1204, 1210 (9th Cir. 2017). The Fifth Circuit came to the opposite conclusion in Brewer v. Wilkinson , 3 F.3d 816, 825 (5th Cir. 1993) (“[W]e must also hold that the violation of the prison regulation requiring that a prisoner be present when his incoming legal mail is opened and inspected is not a violation of prisoner’s constitutional rights.”). ↑

  Brewer , 3 F.3d at 822 (citing Wolff , 418 U.S. at 577). ↑

 Id. at 825–26 (“Although the [ Thornburgh ] Court appeared to draw a distinction between incoming and outgoing mail and to preserve the viability of Martinez with respect to outgoing mail, its ‘reading’ of Martinez in Thornburgh suggests that Turner ‘s ‘legitimate penological interest’ test would also be applied to outgoing mail.” (citations omitted)). ↑

  See Lenient in Theory , supra note 8, at 1026. ↑

  See Robert L. Stern & Eugene Gressman, Supreme Court Practice 109–10, 112 (3d ed. 1962). ↑

  See, e.g. , Brewer v. Wilkinson, 3 F.3d 816, 825 (5th Cir. 1993) (holding that Wolff does not mandate an inmate be present for the opening of legal mail and that the principles of Turner can be used to analyze outgoing mail challenges, rather than the principles of Procunier v. Martinez ). ↑

  See Sup. Ct. R. 10 (listing the character of reasons for granting review on writ of certiorari, including where federal court of appeals “has entered a decision in conflict with the decision of another United States court of appeals on the same important matter” and where a federal court of appeals “has decided an important federal question in a way that conflicts with relevant decisions of this Court”). ↑

  Turner v. Safley, 482 U.S. 78, 89 (1987) (“Subjecting the day-to-day judgments of prison officials to an inflexible strict scrutiny analysis would seriously hamper their ability to anticipate security problems and to adopt innovative solutions to the intractable problems of prison administration.”) ↑

  RLUIPA, 42 U.S.C. § 2000cc-1. First Amendment free exercise in federal and state prisons was originally protected by strict scrutiny under the Religious Freedom Restoration Act of 1993 (“RFRA”), but the Supreme Court held the Act unconstitutional as applied to states and localities in the 1997 case of City of Boerne v. Flores , 521 U.S. 507, 532–36 (1997). Congress responded three years after City of Boerne by passing RLUIPA, which was far less sweeping than the original RFRA provision and applies solely to land use and prisons. Cutter v. Wilkinson, 544 U.S. 709, 715 (2005). ↑

  See Lenient in Theory , supra note 8, at 1021–25. ↑

  RLUIPA, 42 U.S.C. § 2000cc-1. ↑

        Michael Keegan, The Supreme Court’s “Prisoner Dilemma:” How Johnson, RLUIPA, and Cutter Re-Defined Inmate Constitutional Claims , 86 Neb. L. Rev. 279, 324–25 (2007). ↑

  See generally O’Lone v. Estate of Shabazz, 482 U.S. 342, 348 (1987) (applying Turner to prison regulation challenges brought under the First Amendment Free Exercise Clause). ↑

  See Lenient in Theory , supra note 8, at 1022 n. 378 (citing Protecting Religious Freedom After Boerne v. Flores Before the Subcomm. on the Constitution of the H. Comm. on the Judiciary , 105th Cong., app. at 66–67 (1997) (Memorandum from Kim Tucker, Deputy Gen. Counsel to Robert A. Butterworth, Att’y Gen. State of Fla. (July 19, 1996))); see also Brief for the United States as Respondent Amici Curiae Supporting Petitioners, Cutter v. Wilkinson, 544 U.S. 709 (2005) (No. 03-9877), 2004 WL 2961153, at *24 (“For more than a decade, the federal Bureau of Prisons has managed the largest correctional system in the Nation under the same heightened scrutiny standard as RLUIPA without compromising prison security, public safety, or the constitutional rights of other prisoners.”). ↑

  See Lenient in Theory , supra note 8, at 1024–25. ↑

       See Derek L. Gaubatz, RLUIPA at Four: Evaluating the Success and Constitutionality of RLUIPA’s Prisoner Provisions , 28 Harv. J.L. & Pub. Pol’y 501, 583 (2005). ↑

  Congress enacted RFRA to overturn the Supreme Court’s ruling in Emp. Div., Dep’t of Hum. Res. v. Smith , 494 U.S. 872 (1990), which held that generally applicable laws that do not target specific religious practices do not violate the free exercise clause. RFRA was meant to restore strict scrutiny review for free exercise claims, which the Court had applied prior to Smith . See Religious Freedom Restoration Act (RFRA) Now Law of Land , Vol. V, No. 5, Corr. L Rep. 65, 67 (1994). The Court’s later decision in City of Boerne , however, gutted the Act, and after Congress responded with RLUIPA, prisoners were left with heightened free exercise protections as compared to the general public. See supra note 255 and accompanying text. ↑

  See Stewart Jay, The Creation of the First Amendment Right to Free Expression: From the Eighteenth Century to the Mid-Twentieth Century , 34 Wm. Mitchell L. Rev. 773 (2008) (providing a comprehensive history of the First Amendment right to free speech in the United States and the values served by the right); see also Evan Bianchi & David Shapiro, Locked Up, Shut Up: Why Speech in Prison Matters , 92 St. John’s L. Rev. 1 (2018) (discussing why speech in prison matters based on the free expression rationales most frequently cited by the Supreme Court). ↑

  See, e.g. , Lee v. Smith, 552 F. App’x 331, 331 (5th Cir. 2014) (per curiam) (summarily upholding the placement of an incarcerated father’s children on his negative mailing list); Stauffer v. Gearhart, 741 F.3d 574, 578 (5th Cir. 2014) (per curiam) (affirming a motion to dismiss on an inmate’s challenge to a regulation as-applied that resulted in the confiscation of several automotive magazines); Lyons v. Skolnik, 502 F. App’x 712, 713 (9th Cir. 2013) (upholding a ban on inmate possession of typewriters, despite the fact that the Nevada Supreme Court ostensibly required typewritten briefs); Samford v. Dretke, 562 F.3d 674, 676 (5th Cir. 2009) (per curiam) (affirming a motion to dismiss for a challenge to a restriction on an incarcerated father’s communication with his two sons). ↑

  Carson, supra note 145, at 3. ↑

  Turner v. Safley, 482 U.S. 78, 100–01 (Stevens, J., dissenting) (“Application of the [ Turner ] standard would seem to permit disregard for inmates’ constitutional rights whenever the imagination of the warden produces a plausible security concern and a deferential trial court is able to discern a logical connection between that concern and the challenged regulation.”). ↑

  • Submit Article for Publication

Holding the Clauses Together: The Exceptions of Article 16(1) and 16(2) of the Indian Constitution

Published by swaraj mandi on 27/01/2022 27/01/2022, introduction, historical overview, exceptions to the article 16(1) & 16(2), references:.

After attaining the Independence, the next and the most foremost task in hand was of preparing the Constitution. A Constitution, which will be firm on safeguarding and enforcing the rights guaranteed and flexible enough to adopt and adapt to the changes of the contemporary world.

But for India, the task seemed nearly impossible because of the presence of nearly all the impediments which any developing nation could ever face.

The situation worsened even more, when the Colonial Rulers started fishing in troubled waters of India. Their policies of division, was a major challenge for the Independent India to overcome.

With liberty, India was now aiming to be a True Republic.

And True Republic must ensure the Fundamental Rights to every citizen!

But considering the then position of India, with a huge diversity of communities and the feeling of distrust and enmity among the communities, the Framers found themselves submerged in the middle of a swamp.

With the different needs of different communities, the allocation of rights in the Charter wasn’t an easy job.

But, after years of discussions and deliberations, the Constituent Assembly finally came up with a Powerful Constitution which prioritized the ‘Doctrine of Equality’ on one hand and also ensured the Upliftment of the Vulnerable on the other.

In this present article, we will try to comprehend the necessity and the proper interpretation of the exceptions provided in Article 16(1) and 16(2) of the Indian Constitution.

The Article 16 of the Constitution was first discussed in the Constituent Assembly, when Sardar Vallabhbhai Patel presented the Interim Report on the subject of Fundamental Rights prepared by the Assembly-nominated members of the Advisory Committee on the 29 th April 1947.

The Clause 5 (Rights of Equality) of the Interim Report which was adopted by the Assembly

on 30 th April 1947, stated that:

 “(a) There shall be equality of opportunity for all citizens in matter of public employment.

 (b) No citizen shall on grounds only of religion, race, caste, sex, descent, place of birth or any of them be ineligible for public office.

(c) Nothing herein contained shall prevent the State from making provision for reservations in favour of classes who, in the opinion of the State, are not adequately represented in the public services.

 (d) Nothing herein contained shall prevent a law being made prescribing that the incumbent of an office to manage, administer or superintend the affairs of a religious or denominational institution or the member of the Governing Body thereof shall be a member of that particular religion or denomination.” [1]

Today, after seven long decades of the Constitution, the Article has been extended.

Presently, Article 16 states that:

“16. Equality of opportunity in matters of public employment.

(1) There shall be equality of opportunity for all citizens in matters relating to employment or appointment to any office under the State.

(2) No citizen shall, on grounds only of religion, race, caste, sex, descent, place of birth, residence or any of them, be ineligible for, or discriminated against in respect of, any employment or office under the State.

(3) Nothing in this article shall prevent Parliament from making any law prescribing, in regard to a class or classes of employment or appointment to an office [under the Government of, or any local or other authority within, a State or Union territory, any requirement as to residence within that State or Union territory] prior to such employment or appointment.

(4) Nothing in this article shall prevent the State from making any provision for the reservation of appointments or posts in favour of any backward class of citizens which, in the opinion of the State, is not adequately represented in the services under the State.

…………………………………………………………………………………………………..

(5) Nothing in this article shall affect the operation of any law which provides that the incumbent of an office in connection with the affairs of any religious or denominational institution or any member of the governing body thereof shall be a person professing a particular religion or belonging to a particular denomination….” [2]

The provisions of the Article 16, enables us to understand the legislative intent behind its formulation. The Article 16 springs out of the Article 14 of the Constitution.

The Article 14 is a huge edifice of which the Article 16 is one of its constituent blocks.

While Article 14 ensures the ‘Doctrine of Equality’ to prevail, the Article 16 tries to keep its extent within the perimeters prescribed by the Article 14.

As per Article 14, “The State shall not deny to any person equality before the law or the equal protection of the laws within the territory of India” . [3]

This Provision enables any Government or its instrumentalities to conform to the Constitutional position while dealing with the matters pertaining to employment and appointment to any office under the State.

As per Article 16(1), the State is bound to follow the Constitutional Guideline of ensuring equality of opportunity in the matters of employment and appointment under the State.

The Article 16(2) supplements the clause 1 of the said Article.

Both of these provisions manifest the legislative intent of making the Doctrine of Equality to be the Ultimate Guiding tool for such matters.

But, since the days of our Freedom Struggle, it was felt by our National Leaders, that to make an Inclusive Government, there should be a larger participation of its subjects, keeping in mind that the adequate representation of the downtrodden groups is ensured and such a participation must not disrupt in any way the smooth functioning of the government.

Sensing such difficulties to attain both simultaneously, the Framers of our Constitution devised a way to ensure the both by way of installing some exceptions.

As earlier discussed, the Article 16 which ensures equality of opportunity in matters of public employment is subject to some exceptions.

As per Article 16(2), “No citizen shall, on grounds only of religion, race, caste, sex, descent, place of birth, residence or any of them, be ineligible for, or discriminated against in respect of, any employment or office under the State” . [4]

It clearly bars the State to differentiate on the basis of residence.

The Article 16(3) empowers the “Parliament from making any law prescribing, in regard to a class or classes of employment or appointment to an office [under the Government of, or any local or other authority within, a State or Union territory, any requirement as to residence within that State or Union territory] prior to such employment or appointment “. [5]

  • Under Art. 16(3), Parliament may make a law to prescribe a requirement as to residence within a State or Union Territory for eligibility to be appointed with respect to specified classes of appointments or posts. Thus, Art. 16(2) which bans discrimination of citizens on the ground of ‘residence’ only in respect of any office or employment under the state, can be qualified as regards residence, and a ‘residential qualification’ imposed on the right of appointment in the State for specified appointments. This provision, therefore, introduces some flexibility, and takes cognizance of the fact that there may be some very good reasons for restricting certain posts in a State for its residents. [6] But, the Article 16(3) has also maintained a safeguard in order to ensure that such a power is not abused. And for that, the position of law is clear that only the Parliament is entitled to utilize this power and the State Legislative units are not. The reason behind this is, that usually the State Legislative Units have to face great local pressures and conferring such powers to the Legislative Assemblies of the States could create severe obstructions in the smooth and proper functioning of the Public Offices.
  • The second exception is provided in the Article 16(5) [7] of the Indian Constitution. Art. 16(5) provides that a law may prescribe that the incumbent of an office in connection with the affairs of a religious or denominational institution, or a member of the governing body thereof, shall belong to the particular religion or denomination. [8] As we were gearing up for our independence, our forefathers encountered a situation pertaining to the religious affairs. Our Constituent Assembly was comprised of members from different political inclinations, starting from Liberals to Radicals, from Nationalists to Socialists. And in such an environment, there were frequent clashes in the perceptions of the members regarding the policy issues. One such topic of clash was this. On one hand, some members wanted to establish a strict socialist order while on the other hand some members were of the opinion of establishing our country on the basis of it’s great ancient heritage. In our Constitution, the Doctrine of Equality occupies a dominant position. Hence, for any individual, this provision may appear contradictory as it enables the member of the particular religion to sit & administer the office of such religious/denominational institution. It can isolate the communities, because for any Religious Institution, no one except a member of that religion will be entitled to sit in such office. Although, this provision was aimed to secure the religious interests of the various communities, but the compartmentalisation of the Religious Institutions is itself an antithesis to the Principles of Equality, as embodied in the Constitution. For a country like India, unless all the communities unanimously express their assent in allowing members from the different religious communities to sit and administer such offices, the spirit of equality will stand defeated to some extent. Indeed, the Constitution must protect the religious interests of the people. But enabling divisive provisions may fuel more to the disintegration of the societal harmony and order.
  • And the third crucial exception is clause 4 of Art.16. [9] Under Art. 16(4), the state may make reservation of appointments or posts in favour of any ‘backward class’ of citizens which, in the opinion of the state, is not adequately represented in the public services under the state. [10] Casteism is one of the remnants of the antiquity, infesting the minds of the people till date. For centuries, it has made the lives of the people miserable. The Framers of our Constitution, never wanted the casteism to prevail after India’s Independence. But Casteism, being a dirt glued to minds of the common man, was very difficult to get rid off. So, for that purpose the Constitution allocated some space to such groups who formed the lower strata of the casteist society. It was a sort of a governmental incentive, guaranteed by the Constitution. Although it should be wrong to include this in the fundamental rights. But this is one of the fundamentals of the Doctrine of Equality. Prior to the decision of the Apex Court, in the matter of the State of Kerala vs. NM Thomas [11] and the subsequent landmark judgment in the Indra Sawhney Case [12] , it has been held that the Article 16(4) is not an exception but rather a facet of the Doctrine of Equality, embodied in the Constitution.

So, the conclusion which can be drawn from the above discussion is that, the State’s prima facie duty is to ensure the Equality of Opportunity in matters of employment in a public office.

Providing such an opportunity will enhance the functioning of the administration.

As it is evident from many pronouncements of the Apex Court that the Efficiency of Administration should never suffer.

The more efficient an Administration will be, the more it will be beneficial to the people in large.

But the Constitution has provided a space for the administration to allow various class of persons such as the socially and educationally backward groups and vice versa to be a part of such administration.

Such a concession has been made in order to provide adequate representation to the members of these groups.

The Constitution supports the idea of an Inclusive Government. And for that purpose, the participation of people from every corner of the Nation is important.

It is the constitutional obligation of the State to ensure both the administrative efficiency and the upliftment of marginalized groups.

And the concessions, provided in the sectors of appointment and employment in the Public Offices serve as a crutch to these handicapped men and women of the society.

But it must always be remembered that the State has to balance both of these tasks. Over-emphasising of any of these tasks will defeat the purpose as engraved in the Constitution.

And for this, the state must rely on the intelligible differentia, whenever it attempts to make some special provisions for these socially and educationally backward groups.

The state is empowered to classify the communities for the purpose of uplifting various marginalized groups, but it must be reasonable, devoid of arbitrariness and must conform to the principles of Nature Justice and Equality.

And there shouldn’t exist any ambiguity with respect to the fact that in any case, Equality will prevail. But such Equality must not be a mechanical equality. It’s important for us to understand that categorizing the equals and unequals as same will itself be against the Principles of Equality.

By Equality, it should be construed that equals should be treated as equals and treating the equals as unequals or unequals as equals will be in complete contradiction to the Doctrine of Equality.

The Various groups which were provided concessions or relaxations under the Articles 16(3) or 16(4) constitute that block of the society which requires immediate aid from the state. But it should not coincide in any way with the broader interest of the nation.

[1] CONSTITUENT ASSEMBLY DEBATES, VOLUME NO. 3, April 30, 1947)

[2] Art. 16, the Constitution of India

[3] Art. 14, the Constitution of India

[4] Art. 16(2), the Constitution of India

[5] Art, 16(3), the Constitution of India

[6] M.P. Jain, Indian Constitutional Law , 1023 (8 th ed., 2018)  

[7] Art. 16(5), the Constitution of India

[9] Art. 16(4), the Constitution of India

[10] Ibid, at 1024.

[11] State of Kerala vs. NM Thomas , AIR 1976 SC 490 : (1976) 2 SCC 310

[12] Indra Sawhney v UOI , AIR 1993 SC 477 : 1992 Supp (3) SCC 217

Share this:

Leave a reply cancel reply.

Avatar placeholder

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Save my name, email, and website in this browser for the next time I comment.

Related Posts

in article 16 case study 1 sue refused

Constitutional Law

Termination of citizenship and dual citizenship.

The Constituent Assembly integrated a generalized provision through Article 11 for the Parliament to modulate the citizenship by law.

in article 16 case study 1 sue refused

Laws Related to Hospitality Industry in India

The hospitality industry's demand in India is continuing to rise as a result of increased business and tourism business activity.

in article 16 case study 1 sue refused

An Analysis of phrases ‘equality before law’ and ‘equal protection of law’ under Article 14

The State shall not deny to any person equality before the law or the equal protection of the laws within the territory of India.

To join our WhatsApp community

Troubleshooting Questions/Suggestions Print the Code of Ethics from www.nar.realtor .

Back Continue

The state shall not make any discrimination (unfairness) among the citizens on the ground of:-

– religion – race – caste – sex – decent – residence – place of birth – any of them, exceptions to article 16(1) and 16(2), under art- 16(3), parliament may take a law to prescribe a requirement as to residence within a state or union territory for eligibility to be...learn more, a.v.s. narsimha rao v. state of andhra pradesh (air-1970), the supreme court declared that part of the act unconstitutional which prescribed a residence qualification for govt. services in...learn more, important cases to understand article 16, balbir kaur vs. steel authority of india ltd. (air 2000 sc 1596), in this case, the apex court held that appointment on compassionate grounds of...learn more, shiv charan singh vs. state of mysore (air-1965), provisions for compulsory retirement of govt servants in public interests do not infringe articles....learn more, randhir singh vs. union of india (air-1982), it has been held that equal pay for equal work although not expressly declared to be a fundamental right is clearly constitutional under....learn more, devdason vs. union of india (air-1964), the supreme court by a majority of 4 to 1 struck down the carry forward rule as unconstitutional on the ground that the power.....learn more, akhil bhartiya sashit karamchari vs. union of india, in this case, while overruling the t. devadasan case, s.c held that the carry forward rule is valid. court held that the ceiling....learn more, n.m thomas vs. state of kerala, it was held that reservation in promotion is valid..... tap learn more button for reading full article & will get some other related articles, landmark judgment (indira sawhney case) known as mandal commission, justice b.p. jeevan reddy, it was a constitutional bench judgment ratio 6:3 (mandal commission). mandal case is..... tap on learn more, e.p. royappa vs. state of tamil nadu 1974 s.c, in this case, justice bhagwati has held that the concept of equality is not limited only to the concept of reasonable..... tap on learn more, ajay hasia vs. khalid mushis 1981, s.c, justice bhagwati held that arbitrariness is antithetical to equality. equality and arbitrariness cannot go hand in hand..... tap on learn more.

IMAGES

  1. Article 16 of Indian constitution with case laws

    in article 16 case study 1 sue refused

  2. can you use case study

    in article 16 case study 1 sue refused

  3. 182 ARTICLE 16 of

    in article 16 case study 1 sue refused

  4. (PDF) Urgently awaiting implementation: The right to be free from

    in article 16 case study 1 sue refused

  5. Article 16. Case

    in article 16 case study 1 sue refused

  6. UK ABANDONS Article 16 Deal Plan

    in article 16 case study 1 sue refused

VIDEO

  1. Suit Seeks to Allow Non-Attorneys to Give Legal Advice

  2. WVNCP Tutorial

  3. Statements, Admissions, Confessions, Omissions

  4. S. 163, 164, 165, and 167 of the Indian Evidence Act

  5. Reforestation Project in Japan

  6. Case Study 16

COMMENTS

  1. Case Interpretations Related to Article 16

    Case #16-2: Respect for Agency. (Revised Case #21-6 May, 1988. Transferred to Article 16 November, 1994. Revised May, 2017.) Client A gave a 180-day exclusive right to sell listing of a commercial property to REALTOR® B, specifying that no "for sale" sign was to be placed on the property.

  2. Commercial Code of Ethics Case Studies

    Sue is not in violation of Article 16, but she is in violation of Article 3 by refusing to cooperate with Laura. Case Study #2 REALTOR® Barbara has an exclusive listing on Sue's property - a banquet hall that seats 2400 people.

  3. Code of Ethics Case Study: Article 16

    If the contact with the seller is made under the provisions of Standard of Practice 16-4, the REALTOR is also able to discuss the terms of a future listing on the property or may enter into a listing to become effective upon the expiration of the current listing. The Panel found REALTOR Bob not in violation of Article 16.

  4. PDF Article One Case Study #1

    2) Is Paul in Violation of Article 11? Article 16 Case Study REALTOR® Barbara has an exclusive listing on Sue's property - a banquet hall that seats 2400 people. An offer for the property is submitted by Buyer Broker Mike. Barbara takes Mike with her to present the offer to Seller Sue later that evening. Sue is interested, but

  5. DOC The Real World Code of Ethics: Practices and Dilemmas

    Sue is not in violation of Article 16, but she is in violation of Article 3 by refusing to cooperate with Laura. Part 5: Summaries and Case Studies of Selected Articles of the Code of Ethics. Exercise: Article 16, Case Study 2. REALTOR® Barbara has an exclusive listing on Sue's property - a banquet hall that seats 2400 people.

  6. Article 16

    Case #16-1: Confidentiality of Cooperating REALTOR®'s Participation (Revised Case #21-5 May, 1988. Transferred to Article 16 November, 1994.) ... as required by Article 16, and that REALTOR® B had refused to divulge the information; and that he had contacted the property owners only after this refusal, citing as his authority the principle ...

  7. Article 16 Case Study

    Review the case study based on Article 16 that you'll find on the following pages, then, answer the questions. ... Case Study REALTOR® Barbara has an exclusive listing on Sue's property. […] Back to: Code of Ethics History; Article 3; CE-Section 6 Exam; Article 16 Case Study; Article 12-16; CE-Section 5 Exam; Article 11 Case Study ...

  8. PDF ARTICLE 16.1 JUST CAUSE PRINCIPLES

    the very beginning article 16 • section 1- principles • in the administration of this article a basic principle shall be that discipline should be corrective in nature, rather than punitive. • also look under m-39 section 115.1 that is almost identical to the language in article 16.1. s states •

  9. Code of Ethics Case Study

    Code of Ethics Case Study - Article 16. Posted by Sue O'Brien on January 16, 2014 in Pro. Standards | 260 Views. Client A gave a 180-day exclusive right to sell listing of a commercial property to Realtor® B, specifying that no "for sale" sign was to be placed on the property. Realtor® B and his sales associates started an intensive ...

  10. Landmark Judgments on Equality of Opportunity in Public Employment

    Article 16(1) also addresses the principle of equal pay for equal work. In the case, Justice V.R Krishna Iyer correctly observed that the benefits of reservation were, by and large, snatched up by the top creamy layer of the backward classes or classes, thus keeping the weakest among the weak always weak and leaving the fortunate layers to ...

  11. Negligence of Multiple Parties: Article 16 in a Personal Injury Case

    If the pedestrian wants to collect their full $100,000, they'll need to sue the auto manufacturer as well and split their claims. Notably, Article 16 applies only to non-economic damages, meaning things like pain and suffering and emotional distress. Medical bills, lost wages, and other economic damages are not limited by Article 16.

  12. What Is Article 16 in a Personal Injury Case?

    Article 16 is a section of the New York Consolidated Laws Civil Practice Laws & Rules (CPLR). explains the law regarding the limited liability of persons who are jointly liable for damages in a personal injury case. Before Article 16 was enacted in 1966, any party responsible for causing an accident could be held liable for the entire amount of ...

  13. Article 16: Case Study Review

    Article 16: Case Study Review. It was a slow summer, so Don decided to initiate an aggressive marketing campaign to build sales. A key part of his new campaign was direct mail advertising. Don obtained a mailing list that included every home in Cedar Creek (a large subdivision).

  14. Rule 1.16 Declining or Terminating Representation

    A lawyer should not accept representation in a matter unless it can be performed competently, promptly, without improper conflict of interest and to completion. Ordinarily, a representation in a matter is completed when the agreed-upon assistance has been concluded. See Rules 1.1, 1.2(c) and 6.5. See also Rule 1.3, Comment [4]. Mandatory Withdrawal

  15. Article 16, Case study 1: Is Sue in violation of Article 16?

    Understanding Article 16 and Constitutional Rights. In scenario 1, it's not clear what Article 16 entails since we lack context or information about Sue or the specific rules contained within Article 16. To determine whether Sue is in violation of Article 16, more information would be needed regarding the content of this Article and the nature ...

  16. The Case of Jehovah's Witness: A Minor Requiring Blood Products

    Case Study History The patient, a 42-year-old white woman, presented to the emergency room with a severe occipital headache of acute onset, mild dizziness, nausea, and vomiting and, later, diplopia. ... The medical chart indicated that the patient was a Jehovah's Witness who refused blood transfusions ("even if it means death") but was ...

  17. What Is Article 16 in a Personal Injury Action?

    Instead, Article 16 applies to noneconomic damages. While economic damages usually come from tangible bills, noneconomic damages are the losses stemming from non-financial causes. They often include: Pain and suffering. Mental anguish. Emotional distress. Lowered quality of life. Loss of enjoyment of life.

  18. Turner's Insurmountable Burden: A Three-Circuit Survey of Prisoner Free

    Turner's Insurmountable Burden: A Three-Circuit Survey of Prisoner Free Speech Claims. By Kristen Schnell *. Abstract. The last case in which the Supreme Court struck down a prison regulation for violating the federal Constitution was the landmark case of Turner v.Safley, handed down nearly thirty-five years ago. Turner also marked the first time the Court established a clear standard to ...

  19. PDF National Association of Realtors®

    Article 16 of the Code of Ethics. REALTORS® shall not engage in any practice or take any action inconsistent with exclusive representation or exclusive brokerage relationship agreements that other REALTORS® have with clients. (Amended 1/04) Standard of Practice 16-1. Article 16 is not intended to prohibit aggressive or innovative business ...

  20. Business Law 1: Chapter 11 Dynamic Study Module Flashcards

    in which a seller agrees to sell all of its production to a single buyer. A ship's captain promised eight crew the wages of two deserters provided the remaining crew completed the voyage. At the end of the voyage, the ship owner refused to honor the captain's promise to the crew. The crew sued to enforce the promise but the court found in favor ...

  21. Holding the Clauses Together: The Exceptions of Article 16(1) and 16(2

    Exceptions to the Article 16(1) & 16(2) As earlier discussed, the Article 16 which ensures equality of opportunity in matters of public employment is subject to some exceptions. ... [11] and the subsequent landmark judgment in the Indra Sawhney Case [12], it has been held that the Article 16(4) is not an exception but rather a facet of the ...

  22. Article 16: Case Study

    Article 16: Case Study. It was a slow summer, so Don decided to initiate an aggressive marketing campaign to build sales. A key part of his new campaign was direct mail advertising. Don obtained a mailing list that included every home in Cedar Creek (a large subdivision). Within Cedar Creek were a number of homes listed for sale with other brokers.

  23. Article 16 of Indian constitution with case laws

    S.C, justice Bhagwati held that arbitrariness is antithetical to equality. Equality and arbitrariness cannot go hand in hand.....tap on learn more. Article 16 guarantees equality of opportunity in matters of appointment in State services test recruitment for government services. The Protections and Rights are provided...